Countable set: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Wcherowi
m Undid revision 589820378 by 78.29.220.228 (talk) Good faith edit, but didn't quite get the job done.
typo
 
(One intermediate revision by one other user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Redirect|Countable|the linguistic concept|Count noun}}
Everyone else wants more traffic. But most don&quot;t learn how to shine at their site that will be insured by the one thing is jammed with traffic just like a Los Angeles freeway at rush hour. Learn further on our favorite related portfolio by clicking [http://app-factory.info/blogs/data-about-lawyers-you-cannot-discover-elsewhere/ App Factory | Data About Lawyers You Cannot Discover Elsewhere]. That&quot;s, they fail to do anywhere near enough keyword marketing research. <br><br>Awarded reading one article will not you an expert make. But I can at least begin to bring you up to date as it pertains to finding customer packed top search phrases. To do so I&quot;ll show four of my holy keyword research guidelines. <br><br>My first rule of thumb is easy. Don&quot;t be satisfied with well-known keywords. I am aware. Looks obvious. But apparently is not. <br><br>For example the term "easter baskets" gets 120 searches/day. While increasing against 420,00 other pages. <br><br>Perhaps not impossible. But I like less of a challenge. Especially when "personalized easter baskets" gets 109 searches/day and only has 615 competitors. <br><br>Start to see the big difference one-word makes? Like the distinction between lightning and a bug, no? Because you get almost the same number of searches without any where near the same number of competing pages. <br><br>The next key principle is to compare the dual verses singular forms to see which is better. Because in regards to the most webmasters have a [http://Www.Wonderhowto.com/search/tendency/ tendency] to pack onto the wrong choice. <br><br>Just take the definition of "gold earrings" It gets 168 daily searches in all engines, and has 1,540,000 competitive pages in Google. While "gold earring" gets 84 daily searches and looks 440,000 competitors. In other words it has less than a third of the opposition for half the searches. So we&quot;re on the right track. Additionally "italian gold earrings" is employed by 5-2 people daily. And just has to fend off 514 pesky rivals. Or everything you may call a slam-dunk. <br><br>Your next keyword research tactic involves catching the low hanging fresh fruit. O-r what I call "orphan keywords." <br><br>Ultimately you are looking keyphrases with less than 1000 competitive pages in Google when searching for the phrase. 500 or-less is much better still. <br><br>Naturally the closer to 10 competitive pages you get for a search term, the more likely it is your page is to fall in-to the top 10. These are true "orphan keywords." So named on account of neglect by your competition. <br><br>Then don&quot;t forget to believe outside the field. The same as your prospective customers do. <br><br>Say you had a practice in California. One term you could consider is "criminal security attorney." That gets 131 searches but people 1,450,000 competitive pages. I&quot;m maybe not wild about those odds. If people fancy to identify further on [http://well-behaved.info/2014/08/20/info-about-lawyers-you-cant-find-elsewhere/ best criminal attorneys colorado], there are heaps of on-line databases people might investigate. Plus the expression really is not to targeted. <br><br>Digging further I came across that "criminal defense lawyer LA" gets 85 daily searches. And just has 11,1100 pages to beat out. Perhaps not bad. <br><br>Searching greater however "criminal defense lawyer manhattan project county" gets 84 daily searches. But just has 575 competitive pages. To study more, consider having a gander at: [http://avqp.info/blogs/data-about-lawyers-you-cannot-discover-elsewhere/ drug possession defense lawyer co]. Paydirt! <br><br>I started with yet again I turned up a search term with full searches at the least within the same ball park because the generic term. Yet with merely a handful of competitive pages to deal with. Rarely do I fail to try this. The truth is you&quot;ll discover many such jewels by thoroughly researching your keyword world. <br><br>Remember that keyword marketing research could BE THE factor that determines the success or failure of your market site. Applying guidelines like these can help you do smarter optimised keyword marketing. Which often will allow you to attract more traffic from search engines more quickly. And traffic is some thing we&quot;re able to all use more of, right?.Hebets & McCallin P.C.<br>1777 S Harrison St #310<br>Denver, CO 80210<br>(303) 756-3231<br><br>If you are you looking for more information regarding [http://independent.academia.edu/AllanWonga/Posts health games] take a look at our site.
{{distinguish2| [[recursively enumerable set|(recursively) enumerable sets]]}}
In [[mathematics]], a '''countable set''' is a [[Set (mathematics)|set]] with the same [[cardinality]] ([[cardinal number|number]] of elements) as some [[subset]] of the set of [[natural number]]s. A set that is not countable is called ''[[uncountable set|uncountable]]''. The term was originated by [[Georg Cantor]]. The elements of a countable set can be counted one at a time and although the counting may never finish, every element of the set will eventually be associated with a natural number.
 
Some authors use ''countable set'' to mean a set with the same cardinality as the set of natural numbers.<ref name="Rudin">For an example of this usage see {{Harv|Rudin|1976|loc=Chapter 2}}</ref>
 
The difference between the two senses of ''countable set'' is in how they handle [[finite set]]s. Under the first definition finite sets are considered to be countable, while under the second definition they are not. To resolve this ambiguity, the term '''at most countable''' is sometimes used for the first definition, and '''countably infinite''' for the second.
 
The term '''denumerable''' can also be used to mean countably infinite,<ref name="Lang">See {{Harv|Lang|1993|loc=&sect;2 of Chapter I}}.</ref> or countable, in contrast with the term '''nondenumerable'''.<ref name="Apostol">See {{Harv|Apostol|1969|loc=Chapter 13.19}}.</ref>
 
==Definition==
A set ''S'' is called '''countable''' if there exists an [[injective function]] ''f'' from ''S'' to the [[natural numbers]] '''N''' = {0, 1, 2, 3, ...}.<ref>Since there is an obvious [[bijection]] between '''N''' and '''N'''* = {1, 2, 3, ...}, it makes no difference whether one considers 0 to be a natural number of not. In any case, this article follows [[ISO 31-11]] and the standard convention in [[mathematical logic]], which make 0 a natural number.</ref>
 
If this ''f'' is also [[surjective function|surjective]] and therefore [[bijection|bijective]], then ''S'' is called '''countably [[infinite set|infinite]].'''
 
In other words, a set is called "countably infinite" if it has [[One-one correspondence|one-to-one correspondence]] with the natural number set, '''N'''.
 
As noted above, this terminology is not universal: Some authors use countable to mean what is here called "countably infinite," and to not include finite sets.
 
For alternative (equivalent) formulations of the definition in terms of a bijective function or a surjective function, see the section [[#Formal definition and properties|Formal definition and properties]] below.
 
==Introduction==
A ''[[Set (mathematics)|set]]'' is a collection of ''elements'', and may be described in many ways. One way is simply to list all of its elements; for example, the set consisting of the integers 3, 4, and 5 may be denoted {3, 4, 5}. This is only effective for small sets, however; for larger sets, this would be time-consuming and error-prone. Instead of listing every single element, sometimes an ellipsis ("...") is used, if the writer believes that the reader can easily guess what is missing; for example, {1, 2, 3, ..., 100} presumably denotes the set of [[integer]]s from 1 to 100. Even in this case, however, it is still ''possible'' to list all the elements, because the set is ''finite''; it has a specific number of elements.
 
Some sets are ''infinite''; these sets have more than ''n'' elements for any integer ''n''. For example, the set of natural numbers, denotable by {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ...}, has infinitely many elements, and we cannot use any normal number to give its size. Nonetheless, it turns out that infinite sets do have a well-defined notion of size (or more properly, of ''cardinality'', which is the technical term for the number of elements in a set), and not all infinite sets have the same cardinality.
 
To understand what this means, we first examine what it ''does not'' mean. For example, there are infinitely many odd integers, infinitely many even integers, and (hence) infinitely many integers overall. However, it turns out that the number of odd integers, which is the same as the number of even integers, is also the same as the number of integers overall. This is because we arrange things such that for every integer, there is a distinct odd integer: ... −2 → −3, −1 → −1, 0 → 1, 1 → 3, 2 → 5, ...; or, more generally, ''n'' → 2''n'' + 1. What we have done here is arranged the integers and the odd integers into a ''one-to-one correspondence'' (or ''[[bijection]]''), which is a [[function (mathematics)|function]] that maps between two sets such that each element of each set corresponds to a single element in the other set.
 
However, not all infinite sets have the same cardinality. For example, [[Georg Cantor]] (who introduced this concept) demonstrated that the [[real number]]s cannot be put into one-to-one correspondence with the natural numbers (non-negative integers), and therefore that the set of real numbers has a greater cardinality than the set of natural numbers.
 
A set is ''countable'' if: (1) it is finite, or (2) it has the same cardinality (size) as the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if it has the same cardinality as some [[subset]] of the set of natural numbers. Otherwise, it is ''uncountable''.
 
==Formal definition and properties==
By definition a set ''S'' is '''countable''' if there exists an [[injective function]] ''f'' : ''S'' → '''N''' from ''S'' to the [[natural numbers]] '''N''' = {0, 1, 2, 3, ...}.
 
It might seem natural to divide the sets into different classes: put all the sets containing one element together; all the sets containing two elements together; ...; finally, put together all infinite sets and consider them as having the same size.
This view is not tenable, however, under the natural definition of size.
 
To elaborate this we need the concept of a [[bijection]]. Although a "bijection" seems a more advanced concept than a number, the usual development of mathematics in terms of set theory defines functions before numbers, as they are based on much simpler sets. This is where the concept of a bijection comes in: define the correspondence
 
:''a'' ↔ 1, ''b'' ↔ 2, ''c'' ↔ 3
 
Since every element of {''a'', ''b'', ''c''} is paired with ''precisely one'' element of {1, 2, 3}, ''and'' vice versa, this defines a bijection.
 
We now generalize this situation and ''define'' two sets to be of the same size if (and only if) there is a bijection between them. For all finite sets this gives us the usual definition of "the same size". What does it tell us about the size of infinite sets?
 
Consider the sets ''A'' = {1, 2, 3, ... }, the set of positive [[integer]]s and ''B'' = {2, 4, 6, ... }, the set of even positive integers. We claim that, under our definition, these sets have the same size, and that therefore ''B'' is countably infinite. Recall that to prove this we need to exhibit a bijection between them. But this is easy, using ''n'' ↔ 2''n'', so that
:1 ↔ 2, 2 ↔ 4, 3 ↔ 6, 4 ↔ 8, ....
 
As in the earlier example, every element of A has been paired off with precisely one element of B, and vice versa. Hence they have the same size. This gives an example of a set which is of the same size as one of its proper subsets, a situation which is impossible for finite sets.
 
Likewise, the set of all [[ordered pair]]s of natural numbers is countably infinite, as can be seen by following a path like the one in the picture: [[File:Pairing natural.svg|thumb|300px|The [[Cantor pairing function]] assigns one natural number to each pair of natural numbers]] The resulting mapping is like this:
:0 ↔ (0,0), 1 ↔ (1,0), 2 ↔ (0,1), 3 ↔ (2,0), 4 ↔ (1,1), 5 ↔ (0,2), 6 ↔ (3,0) ....
It is evident that this mapping will cover all such ordered pairs.
 
Interestingly: if you treat each pair as being the [[numerator]] and [[denominator]] of a [[vulgar fraction]], then for every positive fraction, we can come up with a distinct number corresponding to it. This representation includes also the natural numbers, since every natural number is also a fraction ''N''/1. So we can conclude that there are exactly as many positive rational numbers as there are positive integers. This is true also for all rational numbers, as can be seen below (a more complex presentation is needed to deal with negative numbers).
 
'''Theorem:''' The [[Cartesian product]] of finitely many countable sets is countable.
 
This form of triangular [[Map (mathematics)|mapping]] [[recursion|recursively]] generalizes to [[vector space|vectors]] of finitely many natural numbers by repeatedly mapping the first two elements to a natural number. For example, (0,2,3) maps to (5,3) which maps to 39.
 
Sometimes more than one mapping is useful. This is where you map the set which you want to show countably infinite, onto another set; and then map this other set to the natural numbers. For example, the positive [[rational number]]s can easily be mapped to (a subset of) the pairs of natural numbers because ''p''/''q ''maps to (''p'', ''q'').
 
What about infinite subsets of countably infinite sets? Do these have fewer elements than '''N'''?
 
'''Theorem:''' Every subset of a countable set is countable. In particular, every infinite subset of a countably infinite set is countably infinite.
 
For example, the set of [[prime number]]s is countable, by mapping the ''n''-th prime number to ''n'':
*2 maps to 1
*3 maps to 2
*5 maps to 3
*7 maps to 4
*11 maps to 5
*13 maps to 6
*17 maps to 7
*19 maps to 8
*23 maps to 9
*...
 
What about sets being "larger than" '''N'''? An obvious place to look would be '''Q''', the set of all [[rational number]]s, which intuitively may seem much bigger than '''N'''. But looks can be deceiving, for we assert:
 
'''Theorem:''' '''Q''' (the set of all rational numbers) is countable.
 
'''Q''' can be defined as the set of all fractions ''a''/''b'' where ''a'' and ''b'' are integers and ''b'' > 0. This can be mapped onto the subset of ordered triples of natural numbers (''a'', ''b'', ''c'') such that ''a'' ≥ 0, ''b'' > 0, ''a'' and ''b'' are [[coprime]], and ''c'' ∈ {0, 1} such that ''c'' = 0 if ''a''/''b'' ≥ 0 and ''c'' = 1 otherwise.
 
*0 maps to (0,1,0)
*1 maps to (1,1,0)
*−1 maps to (1,1,1)
*1/2 maps to (1,2,0)
*−1/2 maps to (1,2,1)
*2 maps to (2,1,0)
*−2 maps to (2,1,1)
*1/3 maps to (1,3,0)
*−1/3 maps to (1,3,1)
*3 maps to (3,1,0)
*−3 maps to (3,1,1)
*1/4 maps to (1,4,0)
*−1/4 maps to (1,4,1)
*2/3 maps to (2,3,0)
*−2/3 maps to (2,3,1)
*3/2 maps to (3,2,0)
*−3/2 maps to (3,2,1)
*4 maps to (4,1,0)
*−4 maps to (4,1,1)
*...
 
By a similar development, the set of [[algebraic number]]s is countable, and so is the set of [[definable number]]s.
 
'''Theorem:''' (Assuming the [[axiom of countable choice]]) The [[union (set theory)|union]] of countably many countable sets is countable.
 
For example, given countable sets '''a''', '''b''', '''c''' ...
 
Using a variant of the triangular enumeration we saw above:
 
*''a''<sub>0</sub> maps to 0
*''a''<sub>1</sub> maps to 1
*''b''<sub>0</sub> maps to 2
*''a''<sub>2</sub> maps to 3
*''b''<sub>1</sub> maps to 4
*''c''<sub>0</sub> maps to 5
*''a''<sub>3</sub> maps to 6
*''b''<sub>2</sub> maps to 7
*''c''<sub>1</sub> maps to 8
*''d''<sub>0</sub> maps to 9
*''a''<sub>4</sub> maps to 10
*...
 
Note that this only works if the sets '''a''', '''b''', '''c''',... are [[disjoint sets|disjoint]]. If not, then the union is even smaller and is therefore also countable by a previous theorem.
 
Also note that the [[axiom of countable choice]] is needed in order to index ''all'' of the sets '''a''', '''b''', '''c''',...
 
'''Theorem:''' The set of all finite-length [[sequence]]s of natural numbers is countable.
 
This set is the union of the length-1 sequences, the length-2 sequences, the length-3 sequences, each of which is a countable set (finite Cartesian product). So we are talking about a countable union of countable sets, which is countable by the previous theorem.
 
'''Theorem:''' The set of all finite [[subset]]s of the natural numbers is countable.
 
If you have a finite subset, you can order the elements into a finite sequence. There are only countably many finite sequences, so also there are only countably many finite subsets.
 
The following theorem gives equivalent formulations in terms of a bijective function or a [[surjective function]]. A proof of this result can be found in Lang's text.<ref name="Lang"/>
 
'''Theorem:''' Let ''S'' be a set. The following statements are equivalent:
# ''S'' is countable, i.e. there exists an injective function ''f'' : ''S'' → '''N'''.
# Either ''S'' is empty or there exists a surjective function ''g'' : '''N''' → ''S''. 
# Either ''S'' is finite or there exists a [[bijection]] ''h'' : '''N''' → ''S''.
 
Several standard properties follow easily from this theorem.  We present them here tersely.  For a gentler presentation see the sections above.  Observe that '''N''' in the theorem can be replaced with any countably infinite set.  In particular we have the following Corollary.
 
'''Corollary:''' Let ''S'' and ''T'' be sets.
# If the function ''f'' : ''S'' → ''T'' is injective and ''T'' is countable then ''S'' is countable.
# If the function ''g'' : ''S'' → ''T'' is surjective and ''S'' is countable then ''T'' is countable.
 
'''Proof:''' For (1) observe that if ''T'' is countable there is an injective function  ''h'' : ''T'' → '''N'''.  Then if ''f'' : ''S'' → ''T'' is injective the composition ''h'' <small> o </small> ''f'' : ''S'' → '''N''' is injective, so ''S'' is countable.
 
For (2) observe that if ''S'' is countable there is a surjective function ''h'' : '''N''' → ''S''.  Then if ''g'' : ''S'' → ''T'' is surjective the composition ''g'' <small> o </small> ''h'' : '''N''' → ''T'' is surjective, so ''T'' is countable.
 
'''Proposition:''' Any subset of a countable set is countable.
 
'''Proof:''' The restriction of an injective function to a subset of its [[domain of a function|domain]] is still injective.
 
'''Proposition:'''  The [[Cartesian product]] of two countable sets ''A'' and ''B'' is countable.
 
'''Proof:''' Note that '''N''' × '''N''' is countable as a consequence of the definition because the function ''f'' : '''N''' × '''N''' → '''N''' given by  ''f''(''m'', ''n'') = 2<sup>''m''</sup>3<sup>''n''</sup> is injective.  It then follows from the Basic Theorem and the Corollary that the Cartesian product of any two countable sets is countable. This follows because if ''A'' and ''B'' are countable there are surjections ''f'' : '''N''' → ''A'' and ''g'' : '''N''' → ''B''. So
:''f'' × ''g'' : '''N''' × '''N''' → ''A'' × ''B''
is a surjection from the countable set '''N''' × '''N''' to the set ''A'' × ''B'' and the Corollary implies ''A'' × ''B'' is countable. This result generalizes to the Cartesian product of any finite collection of countable sets and the proof follows by [[mathematical induction|induction]] on the number of sets in the collection.
 
'''Proposition:''' The [[integers]] '''Z''' are countable and the [[rational numbers]] '''Q''' are countable.
 
'''Proof:''' The integers '''Z''' are countable because the function ''f'' : '''Z''' → '''N''' given by ''f''(''n'') = 2<sup>''n''</sup> if ''n'' is non-negative and ''f''(''n'') = 3<sup>|''n''|</sup> if ''n'' is negative is an injective function. The rational numbers '''Q''' are countable because the function ''g'' : '''Z''' × '''N''' → '''Q''' given by ''g''(''m'', ''n'') = ''m''/(''n'' + 1) is a surjection from the countable set '''Z''' × '''N''' to the rationals '''Q'''.
 
'''Proposition:''' If ''A<sub>n</sub>'' is a countable set for each ''n'' in '''N''' then the union of all ''A<sub>n</sub>'' is also countable.
 
'''Proof:''' This is a consequence of the fact that for each ''n'' there is a surjective function ''g<sub>n</sub>'' : '''N''' → ''A<sub>n</sub>'' and hence the function
:<math>G : \mathbf{N} \times \mathbf{N} \to \bigcup_{n \in \mathbf{N}} A_n</math>
given by ''G''(''n'', ''m'') = ''g<sub>n</sub>''(''m'') is a surjection. Since '''N''' × '''N''' is countable, the Corollary implies that the union is countable. We are using the [[axiom of countable choice]] in this proof in order to pick for each ''n'' in '''N''' a surjection ''g<sub>n</sub>'' from the non-empty collection of surjections from '''N''' to ''A<sub>n</sub>''.
 
'''[[Cantor's Theorem]]''' asserts that if ''A'' is a set and ''P''(''A'') is its [[power set]], i.e. the set of all subsets of ''A'', then there is no surjective function from ''A'' to ''P''(''A'').  A proof is given in the article [[Cantor's Theorem]].  As an immediate consequence of this and the Basic Theorem above we have:
 
'''Proposition:''' The set ''P''('''N''') is not countable; i.e. it is [[uncountable]].
 
For an elaboration of this result see [[Cantor's diagonal argument]].
 
The set of [[real number]]s is uncountable (see [[Cantor's first uncountability proof]]), and so is the set of all infinite [[sequence]]s of natural numbers.  A topological proof for the uncountability of the real numbers is described at [[finite intersection property]].
 
==Minimal model of set theory is countable==
If there is a set that is a standard model (see [[inner model]]) of ZFC set theory, then there is a minimal standard model (''see'' [[Constructible universe]]). The [[Löwenheim-Skolem theorem]] can be used to show that this minimal model is countable. The fact that the notion of "uncountability" makes sense even in this model, and in particular that this model ''M'' contains elements which are
* subsets of ''M'', hence countable,
* but uncountable from the point of view of ''M'',
was seen as paradoxical in the early days of set theory, see [[Skolem's paradox]].
 
The minimal standard model includes all the [[algebraic number]]s and all effectively computable [[transcendental number]]s, as well as many other kinds of numbers.
 
==Total orders==
Countable sets can be [[total order|totally ordered]] in various ways, e.g.:
*[[Well order]]s (see also [[ordinal number]]):
**The usual order of natural numbers (0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ...)
**The integers in the order (0, 1, 2, 3, ...; −1, −2, −3, ...)
*Other (''not'' well orders):
**The usual order of integers (..., -3, -2, -1, 0, 1, 2, 3, ...)
**The usual order of rational numbers (Cannot be explicitly written as a list!)
 
Note that in both examples of well orders here, any subset has a ''least element''; and in both examples of non-well orders, ''some'' subsets do not have a ''least element''.
This is the key definition that determines whether a total order is also a well order.
 
==See also==
{{Wiktionary|countable}}
* [[Aleph number]]
* [[Counting]]
* [[Hilbert's paradox of the Grand Hotel]]
* [[Uncountable set]]
 
==Notes==
<references/>
 
==References==
* {{Citation | last1=Lang | first1=Serge | author1-link=Serge Lang | title=Real and Functional Analysis | publisher=[[Springer-Verlag]] | location=Berlin, New York | isbn=0-387-94001-4 | year=1993}}
* {{Citation | last1=Rudin | first1=Walter | author1-link=Walter Rudin | title=Principles of Mathematical Analysis | publisher=[[McGraw-Hill]]| location=New York | isbn=0-07-054235-X | year=1976}}
 
== External links ==
*{{MathWorld |title=Countable Set |id=CountableSet }}
 
{{logic}}
{{Set theory}}
 
[[Category:Basic concepts in infinite set theory]]
[[Category:Cardinal numbers]]
[[Category:Infinity]]
 
{{Link FA|lmo}}

Latest revision as of 23:42, 5 January 2015

Everyone else wants more traffic. But most don"t learn how to shine at their site that will be insured by the one thing is jammed with traffic just like a Los Angeles freeway at rush hour. Learn further on our favorite related portfolio by clicking App Factory | Data About Lawyers You Cannot Discover Elsewhere. That"s, they fail to do anywhere near enough keyword marketing research.

Awarded reading one article will not you an expert make. But I can at least begin to bring you up to date as it pertains to finding customer packed top search phrases. To do so I"ll show four of my holy keyword research guidelines.

My first rule of thumb is easy. Don"t be satisfied with well-known keywords. I am aware. Looks obvious. But apparently is not.

For example the term "easter baskets" gets 120 searches/day. While increasing against 420,00 other pages.

Perhaps not impossible. But I like less of a challenge. Especially when "personalized easter baskets" gets 109 searches/day and only has 615 competitors.

Start to see the big difference one-word makes? Like the distinction between lightning and a bug, no? Because you get almost the same number of searches without any where near the same number of competing pages.

The next key principle is to compare the dual verses singular forms to see which is better. Because in regards to the most webmasters have a tendency to pack onto the wrong choice.

Just take the definition of "gold earrings" It gets 168 daily searches in all engines, and has 1,540,000 competitive pages in Google. While "gold earring" gets 84 daily searches and looks 440,000 competitors. In other words it has less than a third of the opposition for half the searches. So we"re on the right track. Additionally "italian gold earrings" is employed by 5-2 people daily. And just has to fend off 514 pesky rivals. Or everything you may call a slam-dunk.

Your next keyword research tactic involves catching the low hanging fresh fruit. O-r what I call "orphan keywords."

Ultimately you are looking keyphrases with less than 1000 competitive pages in Google when searching for the phrase. 500 or-less is much better still.

Naturally the closer to 10 competitive pages you get for a search term, the more likely it is your page is to fall in-to the top 10. These are true "orphan keywords." So named on account of neglect by your competition.

Then don"t forget to believe outside the field. The same as your prospective customers do.

Say you had a practice in California. One term you could consider is "criminal security attorney." That gets 131 searches but people 1,450,000 competitive pages. I"m maybe not wild about those odds. If people fancy to identify further on best criminal attorneys colorado, there are heaps of on-line databases people might investigate. Plus the expression really is not to targeted.

Digging further I came across that "criminal defense lawyer LA" gets 85 daily searches. And just has 11,1100 pages to beat out. Perhaps not bad.

Searching greater however "criminal defense lawyer manhattan project county" gets 84 daily searches. But just has 575 competitive pages. To study more, consider having a gander at: drug possession defense lawyer co. Paydirt!

I started with yet again I turned up a search term with full searches at the least within the same ball park because the generic term. Yet with merely a handful of competitive pages to deal with. Rarely do I fail to try this. The truth is you"ll discover many such jewels by thoroughly researching your keyword world.

Remember that keyword marketing research could BE THE factor that determines the success or failure of your market site. Applying guidelines like these can help you do smarter optimised keyword marketing. Which often will allow you to attract more traffic from search engines more quickly. And traffic is some thing we"re able to all use more of, right?.Hebets & McCallin P.C.
1777 S Harrison St #310
Denver, CO 80210
(303) 756-3231

If you are you looking for more information regarding health games take a look at our site.