|
|
(One intermediate revision by one other user not shown) |
Line 1: |
Line 1: |
| [[File:Schroedingers cat film.svg|thumb|right|350px|The quantum-mechanical "[[Schrödinger's cat]]" paradox according to the many-worlds interpretation. In this interpretation, every event is a branch point; the cat is both alive and dead, even before the box is opened, but the "alive" and "dead" cats are in different branches of the universe, both of which are equally real, but which do not interact with each other.<ref name=dewitt71/>]]
| | Eloy may be the name people use to call me and I totally dig that reputation. I used end up being unemployed however right now I am an invoicing officer and I'll be promoted early. To draw 3d graphics precisely what love accomplishing. He currently lives in Guam but his wife wants them to keep.<br><br>Here is my web-site; [https://qtrial2014.az1.qualtrics.com/SE/?SID=SV_3loc6jN5htnRrVj&Preview=Survey&BrandID=qtrial2014/ Services] |
| | |
| The '''many-worlds interpretation''' is an [[interpretations of quantum mechanics|interpretation of quantum mechanics]] that asserts the [[Philosophical realism|objective reality]] of the [[universal wavefunction]] and denies the actuality of [[wavefunction collapse]]. Many-worlds implies that all [[probability|possible]] [[Alternate history|alternative histories]] and futures are real, each representing an actual "world" (or "universe"). In lay terms, the hypothesis states there is a very large—perhaps infinite<ref name="Heresy">{{cite journal | last1 = Osnaghi | first1 = Stefano | last2 = Freitas | first2 = Fabio | last3 = Olival Freire | first3 = Jr | authorlink3 = Olival Freire, Jr. | year = 2009 | title = The Origin of the Everettian Heresy | url = http://stefano.osnaghi.free.fr/Everett.pdf | format = PDF | journal = Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics | volume = 40 | issue = | pages = 97–123 | doi=10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.10.002}}</ref>—number of universes, and everything that could possibly have happened in our past, but did not, has occurred in the past of some other universe or universes. The theory is also referred to as '''MWI''', the '''relative state formulation''', the '''Everett interpretation''', the '''theory of the universal wavefunction''', '''many-universes interpretation''', or just '''many-worlds'''.
| |
| | |
| The original relative state formulation is due to [[Hugh Everett III|Hugh Everett]] in 1957.<ref name=everett56>[[Hugh Everett]] [http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/manyworlds/pdf/dissertation.pdf Theory of the Universal Wavefunction], Thesis, Princeton University, (1956, 1973), pp 1–140</ref><ref name=everett57>{{cite journal | last1 = Everett | first1 = Hugh | authorlink = Hugh Everett | year = 1957 | title = Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics | url = http://www.univer.omsk.su/omsk/Sci/Everett/paper1957.html | journal = Reviews of Modern Physics | volume = 29 | issue = | pages = 454–462 |bibcode = 1957RvMP...29..454E |doi = 10.1103/RevModPhys.29.454 }}</ref> Later, this formulation was popularized and renamed ''many-worlds'' by [[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]] in the 1960s and 1970s.<ref name=dewitt71>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]], Quantum Mechanics and Reality: Could the solution to the dilemma of indeterminism be a universe in which all possible outcomes of an experiment actually occur?, ''Physics Today'', 23(9) pp 30–40 (September 1970) "every quantum transition taking place on every star, in every galaxy, in every remote corner of the universe is splitting our local world on earth into myriads of copies of itself." See also ''Physics Today'', letters followup, 24(4), (April 1971), pp 38–44</ref><ref name=dewitt67>[[Cecile M. DeWitt]], [[John A. Wheeler]] eds, The Everett–Wheeler Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, ''Battelle Rencontres: 1967 Lectures in Mathematics and Physics'' (1968)</ref><ref name=dewitt72>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]], The Many-Universes Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, ''Proceedings of the International School of Physics "Enrico Fermi" Course IL: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', [[Academic Press]] (1972)</ref><ref name=dewitt73>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]], [[R. Neill Graham]], eds, ''The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics'', Princeton Series in Physics, [[Princeton University Press]] (1973), ISBN 0-691-08131-X Contains Everett's thesis: The Theory of the Universal Wavefunction, pp 3–140.</ref> The decoherence approaches to interpreting quantum theory have been further explored and developed,<ref name=zeh>[[H. Dieter Zeh]], On the Interpretation of Measurement in Quantum Theory, ''Foundation of Physics'', vol. 1, pp. 69–76, (1970).</ref><ref name=zurek91>[[Wojciech Hubert Zurek]], Decoherence and the transition from quantum to classical, ''Physics Today'', vol. 44, issue 10, pp. 36–44, (1991).</ref><ref name=zurek03>[[Wojciech Hubert Zurek]], Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical, ''Reviews of Modern Physics'', 75, pp 715–775, (2003)</ref> becoming quite popular. MWI is one of many multiverse hypotheses in [[physics]] and [[philosophy]]. It is currently considered a mainstream interpretation along with the other decoherence interpretations, the [[Copenhagen interpretation]],<ref>[http://www.hep.upenn.edu/~max/everett.ps The Many Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics]</ref> and deterministic interpretations such as the [[De Broglie–Bohm theory|Bohmian mechanics]].
| |
| | |
| Before many-worlds, reality had always been viewed as a single unfolding history. Many-worlds, however, views reality as a many-branched tree, wherein every possible quantum outcome is realised.<ref>[[David Deutsch]] argues that a great deal of fiction is close to a fact somewhere in the so called [[multiverse]], ''Beginning of Infinity'', p. 294</ref> Many-worlds claims to reconcile the observation of non-[[Determinism|deterministic]] events, such as the [[Radioactive decay|random radioactive decay]], with the fully deterministic [[partial differential equations|equations]] of [[quantum physics]].
| |
| | |
| In many-worlds, the [[Phenomenalism|subjective appearance]] of wavefunction collapse is explained by the mechanism of [[quantum decoherence]], and this is supposed to resolve all of the [[quantum paradox|correlation paradoxes]] of [[Quantum mechanics|quantum theory]], such as the [[EPR paradox]]<ref name=dewitt73paradox>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]], [[R. Neill Graham]], eds, ''The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics'', Princeton Series in Physics, [[Princeton University Press]] (1973), ISBN 0-691-08131-X Contains Everett's thesis: The Theory of the Universal Wavefunction, where the claim to resolves all paradoxes is made on pg 118, 149.</ref><ref name=everett57paradox>[[Hugh Everett]], [http://www.univer.omsk.su/omsk/Sci/Everett/paper1957.html Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics], ''Reviews of Modern Physics'' vol 29, (July 1957) pp 454–462. The claim to resolve EPR is made on page 462</ref> and [[Schrödinger's cat]],<ref name=dewitt71/> since every possible outcome of every event defines or exists in its own "history" or "world".
| |
|
| |
| {{Quantum mechanics|cTopic=[[Interpretation of quantum mechanics|Interpretations]]}}
| |
| | |
| ==Outline==
| |
| [[File:Hugh-Everett.jpg||188px|thumb|right|Hugh Everett (1930–1982) was the first [[physicist]] who proposed the many-worlds interpretation (MWI) of [[quantum physics]], which he termed his "relative state" formulation.]]
| |
| Although several versions of many-worlds have been proposed since [[Hugh Everett]]'s original work,<ref name=everett57/> they all contain one key idea: the equations of physics that model the time evolution of systems ''without'' embedded observers are sufficient for modelling systems which ''do'' contain observers; in particular there is no observation-triggered [[wave function collapse]] which the [[Copenhagen interpretation]] proposes. Provided the theory is [[linear]] with respect to the wavefunction, the exact form of the [[quantum]] dynamics modelled, be it the non-relativistic [[Schrödinger equation]], [[relativistic quantum field theory]] or some form of [[quantum gravity]] or [[string theory]], does not alter the validity of MWI since MWI is a [[metatheory]] applicable to all linear [[quantum mechanics|quantum theories]], and there is no experimental evidence for any non-linearity of the wavefunction in physics.<ref name="weinberglinearitydoft"/><ref name="weinberglinearityannalsop"/> MWI's main conclusion is that the universe (or [[multiverse]] in this context) is composed of a [[quantum superposition]] of very many, possibly even [[Uncountable set|non-denumerably]] [[Infinity|infinitely]]<ref name="Heresy"/> many, increasingly divergent, non-communicating parallel universes or quantum worlds.<ref name=dewitt73/>
| |
| | |
| The idea of MWI originated in Everett's [[Princeton University|Princeton]] [[Doctor of Philosophy|Ph.D.]] thesis "The Theory of the [[Universal Wavefunction]]",<ref name=dewitt73/> developed under his thesis advisor [[John Archibald Wheeler]], a shorter summary of which was published in 1957 entitled "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics" (Wheeler contributed the title "relative state";<ref name=wheeler>[[John Archibald Wheeler]], ''Geons, Black Holes & Quantum Foam'', ISBN 0-393-31991-1. pp 268–270</ref> Everett originally called his approach the "Correlation Interpretation", where "correlation" refers to [[quantum entanglement]]). The phrase "many-worlds" is due to [[Bryce DeWitt]],<ref name=dewitt73/> who was responsible for the wider popularisation of Everett's theory, which had been largely ignored for the first decade after publication. DeWitt's phrase "many-worlds" has become so much more popular than Everett's "Universal Wavefunction" or Everett–Wheeler's "Relative State Formulation" that many forget that this is only a difference of terminology; the content of both of Everett's papers and DeWitt's popular article is the same.
| |
| | |
| The many-worlds interpretation shares many similarities with later, other "post-Everett" interpretations of quantum mechanics which also use [[decoherence]] to explain the process of measurement or wavefunction collapse. MWI treats the other histories or worlds as real since it regards the universal wavefunction as the "basic physical entity"<ref name="reality wf57">Everett 1957, section 3, 2nd paragraph, 1st sentence</ref> or "the fundamental entity, obeying at all times a deterministic wave equation".<ref name="reality wf73">Everett [1956]1973, "Theory of the Universal Wavefunction", chapter 6 (e)</ref> The other decoherent interpretations, such as [[consistent histories]], the [[Existential Interpretation]] etc., either regard the extra quantum worlds as metaphorical in some sense, or are [[Agnosticism|agnostic]] about their reality; it is sometimes hard to distinguish between the different varieties. MWI is distinguished by two qualities: it assumes [[philosophical realism|realism]],<ref name="reality wf57"/><ref name="reality wf73"/> which it assigns to the wavefunction, and it has the minimal formal structure possible, rejecting any [[hidden variable theory|hidden variables]], [[quantum potential]], any form of a collapse postulate (i.e., [[Copenhagen Interpretation|Copenhagenism]]) or mental postulates (such as the [[many-minds interpretation]] makes).
| |
| | |
| Decoherent interpretations of many-worlds using [[einselection]] to explain how a small number of classical pointer states can emerge from the enormous Hilbert space of superpositions have been proposed by [[Wojciech H. Zurek]]. "Under scrutiny of the environment, only pointer states remain unchanged. Other states decohere into mixtures of stable pointer states that can persist, and, in this sense, exist: They are einselected."<ref name="ZurekNature2009">{{cite journal | last = Zurek | first = Wojciech | authorlink = Wojciech Hubert Zurek | title = Quantum Darwinism | publisher = Nature Physics | date = March 2009 | arxiv = 0903.5082 |bibcode = 2009NatPh...5..181Z |doi = 10.1038/nphys1202 | volume=5 | issue=3}}</ref> These ideas complement MWI and bring the interpretation in line with our perception of reality.
| |
| | |
| Many-worlds is often referred to as a [[theory]], rather than just an interpretation, by those who propose that many-worlds can make testable predictions (such as [[David Deutsch]]) or is [[Falsifiability|falsifiable]] (such as Everett) or by those who propose that all the other, non-MW interpretations, are inconsistent, illogical or unscientific in their handling of measurements; [[Hugh Everett]] argued that his formulation was a [[metatheory]], since it made statements about other interpretations of quantum theory; that it was the "only completely coherent approach to explaining both the contents of quantum mechanics and the appearance of the world."<ref name=autogenerated2>[http://space.mit.edu/home/tegmark/everett/ Everett<!-- Bot generated title -->]</ref> Deutsch is dismissive that many-worlds is an "interpretation", saying that calling it an interpretation "is like talking about dinosaurs as an 'interpretation' of fossil records."<ref name="MAD"/>
| |
| | |
| ==Interpreting wavefunction collapse==
| |
| As with the other interpretations of quantum mechanics, the many-worlds interpretation is motivated by behavior that can be illustrated by the [[double-slit experiment]]. When [[photon|particles of light]] (or anything else) are passed through the double slit, a calculation assuming wave-like behavior of light can be used to identify where the particles are likely to be observed. Yet when the particles are observed in this experiment, they appear as particles (i.e., at definite places) and not as non-localized waves.
| |
| | |
| Some versions of the [[Copenhagen interpretation]] of quantum mechanics proposed a process of "[[wavefunction collapse|collapse]]" in which an indeterminate quantum system would probabilistically collapse down onto, or select, just one determinate outcome to "explain" this phenomenon of observation. Wavefunction collapse was widely regarded as artificial and ''ad hoc''{{Citation needed|date=February 2013}}, so an alternative interpretation in which the behavior of measurement could be understood from more fundamental physical principles was considered desirable.
| |
| | |
| Everett's Ph.D. work provided such an alternative interpretation. Everett stated that for a composite system – for example a subject (the "observer" or measuring apparatus) observing an object (the "observed" system, such as a particle) – the statement that either the observer or the observed has a well-defined state is meaningless; in modern parlance, the observer and the observed have become [[quantum entanglement|entangled]]; we can only specify the state of one ''relative'' to the other, i.e., the state of the observer and the observed are correlated ''after'' the observation is made. This led Everett to derive from the unitary, deterministic dynamics alone (i.e., without assuming wavefunction collapse) the notion of a ''relativity of states''.
| |
| | |
| Everett noticed that the unitary, deterministic dynamics alone decreed that after an observation is made each element of the [[quantum superposition]] of the combined subject–object wavefunction contains two "relative states": a "collapsed" object state and an associated observer who has observed the same collapsed outcome; what the observer sees and the state of the object have become correlated by the act of measurement or observation. The subsequent evolution of each pair of relative subject–object states proceeds with complete indifference as to the presence or absence of the other elements, ''as if'' wavefunction collapse has occurred, which has the consequence that later observations are always consistent with the earlier observations. Thus the ''appearance'' of the object's wavefunction's collapse has emerged from the unitary, deterministic theory itself. (This answered Einstein's early criticism of quantum theory, that the theory should define what is observed, not for the observables to define the theory).<ref name="einstein26">"Whether you can observe a thing or not depends on the theory which you use. It is the theory which decides what can be observed." [[Albert Einstein]] to [[Werner Heisenberg]], objecting to placing observables at the heart of the new quantum mechanics, during Heisenberg's 1926 lecture at Berlin; related by Heisenberg in 1968, quoted by [[Abdus Salam]], ''Unification of Fundamental Forces'', Cambridge University Press (1990) ISBN 0-521-37140-6, pp 98–101</ref> Since the wavefunction appears to have collapsed then, Everett reasoned, there was no need to actually assume that it had collapsed. And so, invoking [[Occam's razor]], he removed the postulate of wavefunction collapse from the theory.
| |
| | |
| ==Probability==
| |
| A consequence of removing [[wavefunction collapse]] from the quantum formalism is that the [[Born rule]] requires derivation, since many-worlds claims to derive its interpretation from the formalism. Attempts have been made, by many-world advocates and others, over the years to ''derive'' the Born rule, rather than just conventionally ''assume'' it, so as to reproduce all the required statistical behaviour associated with quantum mechanics. There is no consensus on whether this has been successful.<ref>N.P. Landsman, [http://www.math.ru.nl/~landsman/Born.pdf "The conclusion seems to be that no generally accepted derivation of the Born rule has been given to date, but this does not imply that such a derivation is impossible in principle."], in ''Compendium of Quantum Physics'' (eds.) F.Weinert, K. Hentschel, D.Greenberger and B. Falkenburg (Springer, 2008), ISBN 3-540-70622-4</ref><ref>Adrian Kent (May 5, 2009), [http://arxiv.org/pdf/0905.0624v1 ''One world versus many: the inadequacy of Everettian accounts of evolution, probability, and scientific confirmation'']</ref><ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Kent | first1 = Adrian | year = 1990 | title = Against Many-Worlds Interpretations | arxiv = gr-qc/9703089 | journal = Int.J.Mod.Phys | volume = A5 | issue = | page = 1745 |bibcode = 1990IJMPA...5.1745K |doi = 10.1142/S0217751X90000805 }}</ref>
| |
| | |
| ===Everett, Gleason and Hartle===
| |
| Everett (1957) briefly derived the Born rule by showing that the Born rule was the only possible rule, and that its derivation was as justified as the procedure for defining probability in [[classical mechanics]]. Everett stopped doing research in theoretical physics shortly after obtaining his Ph.D., but his work on probability has been extended by a number of people. [[Andrew Gleason]] (1957) and [[James Hartle]] (1965) independently reproduced Everett's work, known as [[Gleason's theorem]]<ref>{{cite journal
| |
| | author = Gleason, A. M.
| |
| | title = Measures on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space
| |
| | journal = [[Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics]]
| |
| | volume = 6
| |
| | year = 1957
| |
| | pages = 885–893
| |
| | mr = 0096113
| |
| | doi = 10.1512/iumj.1957.6.56050}}
| |
| </ref><ref>[[James Hartle]], Quantum Mechanics of Individual Systems, ''American Journal of Physics'', 1968, vol 36 (#8), pp. 704–712</ref> which was later extended.<ref>E. Farhi, J. Goldstone & S. Gutmann. ''How probability arises in quantum mechanics.'', Ann. Phys. (N.Y.) 192, 368–382 (1989).</ref><ref>{{cite journal
| |
| | author = Pitowsky, I.
| |
| | year = 2005
| |
| | page = 10095
| |
| | journal = Eprint arXiv:quant-ph/0510095
| |
| | title = Quantum mechanics as a theory of probability
| |
| | arxiv = quant-ph/0510095
| |
| | bibcode = 2005quant.ph.10095P}}</ref>
| |
| | |
| ===De Witt and Graham===
| |
| [[Bryce De Witt]] and his doctoral student R. Neill Graham later provided alternative (and longer) derivations to Everett's derivation of the Born rule. They demonstrated that the [[Normed vector space|norm]] of the worlds where the usual statistical rules of quantum theory broke down vanished, in the limit where the number of measurements went to infinity.
| |
| | |
| ===Deutsch ''et al.''===
| |
| An [[information theory|information-theoretic]] derivation of the Born rule from Everettarian assumptions, was produced by [[David Deutsch]] (1999)<ref>Deutsch, D. (1999). Quantum Theory of Probability and Decisions. ''Proceedings of the Royal Society of London'' A455, 3129–3137. [http://www.arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9906015].</ref> and refined by Wallace (2002–2009)<ref>David Wallace: [http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0211104 Quantum Probability and Decision Theory, Revisited]</ref><ref>David Wallace. Everettian Rationality: defending Deutsch’s approach to probability in the Everett interpretation. Stud. Hist. Phil. Mod. Phys. 34 (2003), 415–438.</ref><ref>David Wallace (2003), [http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0312157 Quantum Probability from Subjective Likelihood: improving on Deutsch's proof of the probability rule]</ref><ref>David Wallace, 2009,[http://arxiv.org/abs/0906.2718 A formal proof of the Born rule from decision-theoretic assumptions]</ref> and Saunders (2004).<ref>Simon Saunders: Derivation of the Born rule from operational assumptions. Proc. Roy. Soc. Lond. A460, 1771–1788 (2004).</ref><ref>Simon Saunders, 2004: [http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0412194 What is Probability?]</ref> Deutsch's derivation is a two-stage proof: first he shows that the number of [[orthonormal basis|orthonormal]] Everett-worlds after a branching is proportional to the conventional [[probability density function|probability density]]. Then he uses game theory to show that these are all equally likely to be observed. The last step in particular has been criticised for [[circular definition|circularity]].<ref name=baker/><ref>H. Barnum, C. M. Caves, J. Finkelstein, C. A. Fuchs, R. Schack: [http://lanl.arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9907024 Quantum Probability from Decision Theory?] ''Proc. Roy. Soc. Lond.'' A456, 1175–1182 (2000).</ref> Some other reviews have been positive, although the status of these arguments remains highly controversial; some theoretical physicists have taken them as supporting the case for parallel universes.<ref name="newsci">{{Cite news | last = Merali | first = Zeeya | title = Parallel universes make quantum sense | magazine = New Scientist | issue = 2622 |date=2007-09-21 | url = http://www.newscientist.com/article/mg19526223.700-parallel-universes-make-quantum-sense.html | accessdate = 2013-11-22 | postscript = <!--None--> }} (Summary only).</ref><ref>[http://www.breitbart.com/article.php?id=paUniverse_sun14_parallel_universes&show_article=1&cat=0 Breitbart.com, Parallel universes exist – study, Sept 23 2007]</ref> In the [[New Scientist]] article, reviewing their presentation at a September 2007 conference,<ref>[http://www.perimeterinstitute.ca/index.php?option=com_content&task=view&id=50&Itemid=83&lecture_id=6167 Perimeter Institute, Seminar overview, Probability in the Everett interpretation: state of play, David Wallace – Oxford University, 21 Sept 2007]</ref><ref>[http://www.perimeterinstitute.ca/manyworlds/ Perimeter Institute, Many worlds at 50 conference, September 21–24, 2007]</ref> Andy Albrecht, a physicist at the University of California at Davis, is quoted as saying "This work will go down as one of the most important developments in the history of science."<ref name="newsci" />
| |
| | |
| [[Wojciech H. Zurek]] (2005)<ref>[[Wojciech H. Zurek]]: [http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0405161v2 Probabilities from entanglement, Born’s rule from envariance], ''Phys. Rev.'' A71, 052105 (2005).</ref> has produced a derivation of the Born rule, where [[decoherence]] has replaced Deutsch's informatic assumptions.<ref>M. Schlosshauer & A. Fine: [http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0312058v3 On Zurek's derivation of the Born rule.] ''Found. Phys.'' 35, 197–213 (2005).
| |
| </ref> Lutz Polley (2000) has produced Born rule derivations where the informatic assumptions are replaced by symmetry arguments.<ref>Lutz Polley, [http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0102113v2 Position eigenstates and the statistical axiom of quantum mechanics], contribution to conference ''Foundations of Probability and Physics'', Vaxjo, Nov 27 – Dec 1, 2000</ref><ref>Lutz Polley, [http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9906124v3 Quantum-mechanical probability from the symmetries of two-state systems]</ref>
| |
| | |
| The Born rule and the collapse of the wave function have been obtained in the framework of the relative-state formulation of quantum mechanics by Armando V.D.B. Assis. He has proved that the Born rule and the collapse of the wave function follow from a game-theoretical strategy, namely the [[Nash equilibrium]] within a von Neumann [[zero-sum game]] between nature and observer.<ref name="Armando-VDB-Assis-QM">
| |
| {{cite journal
| |
| |author = Armando V.D.B. Assis
| |
| |year = 2011
| |
| |title = Assis, Armando V.D.B. On the nature of <math>\scriptstyle a^{*}_{k}a_{k}</math> and the emergence of the Born rule. Annalen der Physik, 2011.
| |
| |url=http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/andp.201100062/abstract
| |
| |journal = Annalen der Physik (Berlin)
| |
| |volume = 523 | pages = 883–897
| |
| |doi= 10.1002/andp.201100062
| |
| |bibcode = 2011AnP...523..883A |arxiv = 1009.1532 }}</ref>
| |
| | |
| ==Properties of the theory==
| |
| * MWI removes the observer-dependent role in the [[quantum measurement]] process by replacing [[wavefunction collapse]] with [[quantum decoherence]]. Since the role of the observer lies at the heart of most if not all "quantum paradoxes," this automatically resolves a number of problems; see for example [[Schrödinger's cat]] [[thought experiment]], the [[EPR paradox]], [[John von Neumann|von Neumann]]'s "boundary problem" and even [[wave-particle duality]]. [[Quantum cosmology]] also becomes intelligible, since there is no need anymore for an observer outside of the universe.
| |
| * MWI is a [[philosophical realism|realist]], [[deterministic]], [[local realism|local]] theory, akin to [[classical physics]] (including the [[theory of relativity]]), at the expense of losing [[counterfactual definiteness]]. MWI achieves this by removing [[wavefunction collapse]], which is indeterministic and non-local, from the [[deterministic]] and [[local realism|local]] equations of [[Quantum mechanics|quantum theory]].<ref name=rubinlocality>[[Mark A. Rubin]], Locality in the Everett Interpretation of Heisenberg-Picture Quantum Mechanics, ''Foundations of Physics Letters'', 14, (2001) , pp. 301–322, {{arxiv|quant-ph/0103079}}</ref>
| |
| * MWI (or other, broader [[multiverse]] considerations) provides a context for the [[anthropic principle]] which may provide an explanation for the [[fine-tuned universe]].<ref>[[Paul C.W. Davies]], ''Other Worlds'', chapters 8 & 9 ''The Anthropic Principle'' & ''Is the Universe an accident?'', (1980) ISBN 0-460-04400-1</ref><ref>[[Paul C.W. Davies]], ''The Accidental Universe'', (1982) ISBN 0-521-28692-1</ref>
| |
| * MWI, being a [[quantum decoherence|decoherent]] formulation, is axiomatically more streamlined than the [[Copenhagen Interpretation|Copenhagen]] and other [[wavefunction collapse|collapse]] interpretations; and thus favoured under certain interpretations of [[Occam's razor]].<ref name="FAQ occam"/>{{Verify credibility|date=March 2013}} Of course there are other decoherent interpretations that also possess this advantage with respect to the collapse interpretations.
| |
| | |
| ==Common objections==
| |
| {{cleanup-list|date=March 2013}}
| |
| * The many-worlds interpretation is very vague about the ways to determine when splitting happens, and nowadays usually the criterion is that the two branches have [[Quantum decoherence|decohered]]. However, present day understanding of decoherence does not allow a completely precise, self-contained way to say when the two branches have decohered/"do not interact", and hence many-worlds interpretation remains arbitrary. This objection is saying that it is not clear what is precisely meant by branching, and point to the lack of self-contained criteria specifying branching.
| |
| ::MWI response: the decoherence or "splitting" or "branching" is complete when the [[quantum measurement|measurement]] is complete. In [[Bra–ket notation|Dirac notation]] a measurement is complete when:
| |
| :::<math>\lang O_i|O_j\rang = \delta_{ij}</math><ref name=dewitt71ortho>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]], Quantum Mechanics and Reality: Could the solution to the dilemma of indeterminism be a universe in which all possible outcomes of an experiment actually occur?, ''Physics Today'', 23(9) pp 30–40 (September 1970); see equation 10</ref>
| |
| ::where <math>O_i</math> represents the observer having detected the object system in the ''i''th state. Before the measurement has started the observer states are identical; after the measurement is complete the observer states are [[Orthonormality|orthonormal]].<ref name=everett57/><ref name=dewitt73/> Thus a measurement defines the branching process: the branching is as well- or ill-defined as the measurement is; the branching is as complete as the measurement is complete – which is to say that the delta function above represents an idealised measurement. Although true "for all practical purposes" in reality the measurement, and hence the branching, is never fully complete, since delta functions are unphysical,<ref>Penrose, R. ''The Road to Reality'', §21.11</ref>
| |
| ::Since the role of the observer and measurement per se plays no special role in MWI (measurements are handled as all other interactions are) there is no need for a precise definition of what an observer or a measurement is — just as in [[Classical mechanics|Newtonian physics]] no precise definition of either an observer or a measurement was required or expected. In all circumstances the [[universal wavefunction]] is still available to give a complete description of reality.
| |
| ::Also, it is a common misconception to think that branches are completely separate. In Everett's formulation, they may in principle [[Quantum interference|quantum interfere]] (i.e., "merge" instead of "splitting") with each other in the future,<ref>
| |
| Tegmark, Max [http://www.arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9709032/ The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Many Worlds or Many Words?], 1998. To quote: "What Everett does NOT postulate: ''“At certain magic instances, the world undergoes some sort of metaphysical 'split' into two branches that subsequently never interact.”'' This is not only a misrepresentation of the MWI, but also inconsistent with the Everett postulate, since the subsequent time evolution could in principle make the two terms...interfere. According to the MWI, there is, was and always will be only one wavefunction, and only decoherence calculations, not postulates, can tell us when it is a good approximation to treat two terms as non-interacting."</ref> although this requires all "memory" of the earlier branching event to be lost, so no observer ever sees two branches of reality.<ref name="davis86"/><ref name=csimon>Christoph Simon, 2009, [http://arxiv.org/abs/0908.0322v1 ''Conscious observers clarify many worlds'']</ref>
| |
| * MWI states that there is no special role nor need for precise definition of measurement in MWI, yet Everett uses the word "measurement" repeatedly throughout its exposition.
| |
| ::MWI response: "measurements" are treated as a subclass of interactions, which induce subject–object correlations in the combined wavefunction. There is nothing special about measurements (such as the ability to trigger a [[wave function collapse]]), that cannot be dealt with by the usual [[Unitarity (physics)|unitary]] time development process.<ref name=everett56/> This is why there is no precise definition of measurement in Everett's formulation, although some other formulations emphasize that measurements must be effectively irreversible or create classical information.
| |
| * The splitting of worlds forward in time, but not backwards in time (i.e., merging worlds), is time asymmetric and incompatible with the time symmetric nature of [[Schrödinger's equation]], or [[CPT invariance]] in general.<ref>Joseph Gerver, The past as backward movies of the future, ''Physics Today'', letters followup, 24(4), (April 1971), pp 46–7</ref>
| |
| ::MWI response: The splitting is time asymmetric; this observed temporal asymmetry is due to the [[boundary conditions]] imposed by the [[Big Bang]]<ref>[[Bryce Seligman DeWitt]], ''Physics Today'',letters followup, 24(4), (April 1971), pp 43</ref>
| |
| * There is circularity in Everett's measurement theory. Under the assumptions made by Everett, there are no 'good observations' as defined by him, and since his analysis of the observational process depends on the latter, it is void of any meaning. The concept of a 'good observation' is the [[Projection (linear algebra)|projection]] postulate in disguise and Everett's analysis simply derives this postulate by having assumed it, without any discussion.<ref>[http://www.mat.univie.ac.at/~neum/manyworlds.txt Arnold Neumaier's comments on the Everett FAQ, 1999 & 2003]</ref>{{Verify credibility|date=March 2013}}
| |
| | |
| ::MWI response: Everett's treatment of observations / measurements covers ''both'' idealised good measurements and the more general bad or approximate cases.<ref>Everett [1956] 1973, "''Theory of the Universal Wavefunction''", chapter V, section 4 "Approximate Measurements", pp. 100–103 (e)</ref> Thus it is legitimate to analyse probability in terms of measurement; no circularity is present.
| |
| | |
| * Talk of probability in Everett presumes the existence of a preferred basis to identify measurement outcomes for the probabilities to range over. But the existence of a preferred basis can only be established by the process of decoherence, which is itself probabilistic<ref name=baker>David J Baker, [http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00002717/01/OutcomeProbEverett.pdf Measurement Outcomes and Probability in Everettian Quantum Mechanics], ''Studies In History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies In History and Philosophy of Modern Physics'', Volume 38, Issue 1, March 2007, Pages 153–169</ref> or arbitrary.<ref name = stappbasis>Henry Stapp, The basis problem in many-world theories, ''Canadian J. Phys.'' 80,1043–1052 (2002) [http://www-physics.lbl.gov/~stapp/bp.PDF]</ref>
| |
| ::MWI response: Everett analysed branching using what we now call the "measurement [[Basis (linear algebra)|basis]]". It is fundamental theorem of quantum theory that nothing measurable or empirical is changed by adopting a different basis. Everett was therefore free to choose whatever basis he liked. The measurement basis was simply the simplest basis in which to analyse the measurement process.<ref name=BrownWallace>[[Harvey Brown (philosopher)|Harvey R Brown]] and David Wallace, ''Solving the measurement problem: de Broglie–Bohm loses out to Everett'', ''Foundations of Physics'' 35 (2005), pp. 517–540. [http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00001659/01/Cushing.pdf]</ref><ref name=rubinbasis>Mark A Rubin (2005), [http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0310186v2 There Is No Basis Ambiguity in Everett Quantum Mechanics], ''Foundations of Physics Letters'', Volume 17, Number 4 / August, 2004, pp 323–341</ref>
| |
| | |
| * We cannot be sure that the universe is a quantum multiverse until we have a [[theory of everything]] and, in particular, a successful theory of [[quantum gravity]].<ref name="penrose"/> If the final theory of everything is non-[[linear]] with respect to [[wave function|wavefunctions]] then many-worlds would be invalid.<ref name="dewitt71"/><ref name="everett57"/><ref name="dewitt67"/><ref name="dewitt72"/><ref name="dewitt73"/>
| |
| | |
| ::MWI response: All accepted [[Quantum mechanics|quantum theories]] of fundamental physics are linear with respect to the wavefunction. While quantum gravity or [[string theory]] may be non-linear in this respect there is no evidence to indicate this at the moment.<ref name="weinberglinearitydoft">[[Steven Weinberg]], ''Dreams of a Final Theory: The Search for the Fundamental Laws of Nature'' (1993), ISBN 0-09-922391-0, pg 68–69</ref><ref name="weinberglinearityannalsop">[[Steven Weinberg]] ''Testing Quantum Mechanics'', Annals of Physics Vol 194 #2 (1989), pg 336–386</ref>
| |
| | |
| * [[Conservation of energy]] is grossly violated if at every instant near-infinite amounts of new matter are generated to create the new universes.
| |
| | |
| ::MWI response: There are two responses to this objection. First, the law of conservation of energy says that energy is conserved ''within each universe''. Hence, even if "new matter" were being generated to create new universes, this would not violate conservation of energy. Second, conservation of energy is not violated since the energy of each branch has to be weighted by its probability, according to the standard formula for the [[Conservation of energy#Quantum theory|conservation of energy in quantum theory]]. This results in the total energy of the multiverse being conserved.<ref name="FAQ energy conservation">[http://www.hedweb.com/manworld.htm#conservation Everett FAQ "Does many-worlds violate conservation of energy?"]</ref>{{Verify credibility|date=March 2013}}
| |
| | |
| * [[Occam's Razor]] rules against a plethora of unobservable universes – Occam would prefer just one universe; i.e., any non-MWI.
| |
| | |
| ::MWI response: Occam's razor actually is a constraint on the complexity of physical theory, not on the number of universes. MWI is a simpler theory since it has fewer postulates.<ref name="FAQ occam">[http://www.hedweb.com/manworld.htm#ockham's Everett FAQ "Does many-worlds violate Ockham's Razor?"]</ref>{{Verify credibility|date=March 2013}} Occams's razor is often cited by MWI adherents as an advantage of MWI.
| |
| | |
| * Unphysical universes: If a state is a superposition of two states <math>\Psi_A</math> and <math>\Psi_B</math>, i.e., <math>\Psi = (a \Psi_A + b \Psi_B)</math>, i.e., weighted by coefficients ''a'' and ''b'', then if <math>b \ll a</math>, what principle allows a universe with vanishingly small probability ''b'' to be instantiated on an equal footing with the much more probable one with probability ''a''? This seems to throw away the information in the probability amplitudes. Such a theory makes little sense.
| |
| | |
| ::MWI response: The magnitude of the coefficients provides the weighting that makes the branches or universes "unequal", as Everett and others have shown, leading the emergence of the [[Born rule|conventional probabilistic rules]].<ref name="dewitt71"/><ref name="everett57"/><ref name="dewitt67"/><ref name="dewitt72"/><ref name="dewitt73"/><ref name="FAQ probability">[http://www.hedweb.com/manworld.htm#probabilities Everett FAQ "How do probabilities emerge within many-worlds?"]</ref>{{Verify credibility|date=March 2013}}
| |
| | |
| * Violation of the [[principle of locality]], which contradicts [[special relativity]]: MWI splitting is instant and total: this may conflict with relativity, since an alien in the Andromeda galaxy can't know I collapse an electron over here before she collapses hers there: the relativity of [[simultaneity]] says we can't say which electron collapsed first – so which one splits off another universe first? This leads to a hopeless muddle with everyone splitting differently. Note: [[EPR paradox|EPR]] is not a get-out here, as the alien's and my electrons need never have been part of the same quantum, i.e., [[entangled]].
| |
| | |
| ::MWI response: the splitting can be regarded as causal, local and relativistic, spreading at, or below, the speed of light (e.g., we are not split by [[Schrödinger's cat]] until we look in the box).<ref name="FAQ splithow">[http://www.hedweb.com/manworld.htm#splitsh Everett FAQ "When does Schrodinger's cat split?"]</ref>{{Verify credibility|date=March 2013}} For [[spacelike]] separated splitting you can't say which occurred first — but this is true of all spacelike separated events, [[simultaneity]] is not defined for them. Splitting is no exception; many-worlds is a local theory.<ref name=rubinlocality/>
| |
| | |
| ==Brief overview==
| |
| [[Image:Many-worlds-bloch.png|thumb|400px|Schematic representation of pair of "smallest possible" quantum mechanical systems prior to interaction: Measured system '''S''' and measurement apparatus '''M'''. Systems such as '''S''' are referred to as 1-[[qubit]] systems.]]
| |
| In Everett's formulation, a measuring apparatus '''M''' and an object system '''S''' form a composite system, each of which prior to measurement exists in well-defined (but time-dependent) states. Measurement is regarded as causing '''M''' and '''S''' to interact. After '''S''' interacts with '''M''', it is no longer possible to describe either system by an independent state. According to Everett, the only meaningful descriptions of each system are relative states: for example the relative state of '''S''' given the state of '''M''' or the relative state of '''M''' given the state of '''S'''. In DeWitt's formulation, the state of '''S''' after a sequence of measurements is given by a quantum superposition of states, each one corresponding to an alternative measurement history of '''S'''.
| |
| | |
| [[Image:Splittings-1.png|thumb|left|350px|Schematic illustration of splitting as a result of a repeated measurement.]]
| |
| For example, consider the smallest possible truly quantum system '''S''', as shown in the illustration. This describes for instance, the spin-state of an electron. Considering a specific axis (say the ''z''-axis) the north pole represents spin "up" and the south pole, spin "down". The superposition states of the system are described by (the surface of) a sphere called the [[Bloch sphere]]. To perform a measurement on '''S''', it is made to interact with another similar system '''M'''. After the interaction, the combined system is described by a state that ranges over a six-dimensional space (the reason for the number six is explained in the article on the Bloch sphere). This six-dimensional object can also be regarded as a quantum superposition of two "alternative histories" of the original system '''S''', one in which "up" was observed and the other in which "down" was observed. Each subsequent binary measurement (that is interaction with a system '''M''') causes a similar split in the history tree. Thus after three measurements, the system can be regarded as a quantum superposition of 8 = 2 × 2 × 2 copies of the original system '''S'''.
| |
| | |
| The accepted terminology is somewhat misleading because it is incorrect to regard the universe as splitting at certain times; at any given instant there is one state in one universe.
| |
| | |
| ==Relative state==
| |
| The goal of the relative-state formalism, as originally proposed by Everett in his 1957 doctoral dissertation, was to interpret the effect of external observation entirely within the mathematical framework developed by [[Paul Dirac]], [[von Neumann]] and others, discarding altogether the ''ad hoc'' mechanism of wave function collapse. Since Everett's original work, there have appeared a number of similar formalisms in the literature. One such idea is discussed in the next section.
| |
| | |
| The relative-state interpretation makes two assumptions. The first is that the wavefunction is not simply a description of the object's state, but that it actually is entirely equivalent to the object, a claim it has in common with some other interpretations. The second is that observation or measurement has no special role, unlike in the [[Copenhagen interpretation]] which considers the wavefunction collapse as a special kind of event which occurs as a result of observation.
| |
| | |
| The many-worlds interpretation is DeWitt's popularisation of Everett's work, who had referred to the combined observer–object system as being split by an observation, each split corresponding to the different or multiple possible outcomes of an observation. These splits generate a possible tree as shown in the graphic below. Subsequently DeWitt introduced the term "world" to describe a complete measurement history of an observer, which corresponds roughly to a single branch of that tree. Note that "splitting" in this sense, is hardly new or even quantum mechanical. The idea of a space of complete alternative histories had already been used in the theory of probability since the mid-1930s for instance to model [[Brownian motion]]. [[Image:Many-worlds.svg|thumb|300px|Partial trace as relative state. Light blue rectangle on upper left denotes system in pure state. Trellis shaded rectangle in upper right denotes a (possibly) mixed state. Mixed state from observation is partial trace of a linear superposition of states as shown in lower right-hand corner.]][[Image:Paths-many-worlds.svg|thumb|right|300px|Successive measurements with successive splittings]]
| |
| | |
| Under the many-worlds interpretation, the [[Schrödinger equation]], or relativistic analog, holds all the time everywhere. An observation or measurement of an object by an observer is modeled by applying the wave equation to the entire system comprising the observer ''and'' the object. One consequence is that every observation can be thought of as causing the combined observer–object's wavefunction to change into a quantum superposition of two or more non-interacting branches, or split into many "worlds". Since many observation-like events have happened, and are constantly happening, there are an enormous and growing number of simultaneously existing states.
| |
| | |
| If a system is composed of two or more subsystems, the system's state will be a superposition of products of the subsystems' states. Once the subsystems interact, their states are no longer independent. Each product of subsystem states in the overall superposition evolves over time independently of other products. The subsystems states have become correlated or [[quantum entanglement|entangled]] and it is no longer possible to consider them independent of one another. In Everett's terminology each subsystem state was now ''correlated'' with its ''relative state'', since each subsystem must now be considered relative to the other subsystems with which it has interacted.
| |
| | |
| ==Comparative properties and possible experimental tests==
| |
| One of the salient properties of the many-worlds interpretation is that it does not require an exceptional method of wave function collapse to explain it. "It seems that there is no experiment distinguishing the MWI from other no-collapse theories such as [[Bohmian mechanics]] or other variants of MWI... In most no-collapse interpretations, the evolution of the quantum state of the Universe is the same. Still, one might imagine that there is an experiment distinguishing the MWI from another no-collapse interpretation based on the difference in the correspondence between the formalism and the experience (the results of experiments)."<ref name="stanford">{{cite web |last=Vaidman |first=Lev |title=Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-manyworlds/ |publisher=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref>
| |
| | |
| However, in 1985, David Deutsch published three related thought experiments which could test the theory vs the Copenhagen interpretation.<ref>Deutsch, D., (1986) ‘Three experimental implications of the Everett interpretation’, in R. Penrose and C.J. Isham (eds.), Quantum Concepts of Space and Time, Oxford: The Clarendon Press, pp. 204–214.</ref> The experiments require macroscopic quantum state preparation and [[quantum erasure]] by a hypothetical quantum computer which is currently outside experimental possibility. Since then Lockwood (1989), Vaidman and others have made similar proposals.<ref name="stanford"/> These proposals also require an advanced technology which is able to place a macroscopic object in a coherent superposition, another task for which it is uncertain whether it will ever be possible. Many other controversial ideas have been put forward though, such as a recent claim that cosmological observations could test the theory,<ref>Page, D., (2000) ‘[http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/gr-qc/0001001 Can Quantum Cosmology Give Observational Consequences of Many-Worlds Quantum Theory?]’</ref> and another claim by Rainer Plaga (1997), published in ''[[Foundations of Physics]]'', that communication might be possible between worlds.<ref name="plaga">{{cite journal | last1 = Plaga | first1 = R. | year = 1997 | title = '[http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/quant-ph/9510007 Proposal for an experimental test of the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics]' | url = | journal = Foundations of Physics | volume = 27 | issue = | pages = 559–577 |arxiv = quant-ph/9510007 |bibcode = 1997FoPh...27..559P |doi = 10.1007/BF02550677 }}</ref> As of 2010, there are no feasible experiments to test the differences between MWI and other theories.
| |
| | |
| ===Copenhagen interpretation===
| |
| In the Copenhagen interpretation, the mathematics of quantum mechanics allows one to predict [[probability|probabilities]] for the occurrence of various events. In the many-worlds interpretation, all these events occur simultaneously. What meaning should be given to these probability calculations? And why do we observe, in our history, that the events with a higher computed probability seem to have occurred more often? One answer to these questions is to say that there is a [[probability measure]] on the space of all possible universes, where a possible universe is a complete path in the tree of branching universes. This is indeed what the calculations seem to give. Then we should expect to find ourselves in a universe with a relatively high probability rather than a relatively low probability: even though all outcomes of an experiment occur, they do not occur in an equal way. As an interpretation which is consistent with the equations, it is hard to find tests of MWI that distinguish it from other mainstream interpretations.
| |
| | |
| ===The universe decaying to a new vacuum state===
| |
| Any event that changes the number of observers in the universe may have experimental consequences.<ref>{{cite arxiv |eprint=gr-qc/0001001 |author1=Page |doi=10.1063/1.1301589 |title=Can Quantum Cosmology Give Observational Consequences of Many-Worlds Quantum Theory? |class=gr-qc |year=2000}}</ref> [[Quantum tunnelling]] to a new [[vacuum state]] would reduce the number of observers to zero (i.e., kill all life).{{Citation needed|date=May 2010}} Some [[Physical cosmology|cosmologists]] argue that the [[universe]] is in a [[False vacuum|false vacuum state]] and that consequently the universe should have already experienced quantum tunnelling to a true vacuum state. This has not happened and is cited as evidence in favor of many-worlds. In some worlds, quantum tunnelling to a true vacuum state has happened but most other worlds escape this tunneling and remain viable. This can be thought of as a variation on [[Quantum suicide and immortality|quantum suicide]].
| |
| | |
| ===Many-minds===
| |
| {{Main|Many-minds interpretation}}
| |
| The ''many-minds'' interpretation is a multi-world interpretation that defines the splitting of reality on the level of the observers' minds. In this, it differs from Everett's many-worlds interpretation, in which there is no special role for the observer's mind.<ref name="plaga" />
| |
| | |
| ==Reception==
| |
| There is a wide range of claims that are considered "many-worlds" interpretations. It was often claimed by those who do not believe in MWI<ref>[[Jeffrey A. Barrett]], ''The Quantum Mechanics of Minds and Worlds'', Oxford University Press, 1999. According to Barrett (loc. cit. Chapter 6) "There are many many-worlds interpretations."</ref> that Everett himself was not entirely clear<ref>{{cite web |last=Barrett |first=Jeffrey A. |title=Everett's Relative-State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics |publisher=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-first=Edward N. |editor-last=Zalta |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/qm-everett/ |year=2010 |edition=Fall 2010}} Again, according to Barrett "It is... unclear precisely how this was supposed to work."</ref> as to what he believed; however, MWI adherents (such as [[Bryce DeWitt|DeWitt]], [[Max Tegmark|Tegmark]], [[David Deutsch|Deutsch]] and others) believe they fully understand Everett's meaning as implying the literal existence of the other worlds. Additionally, recent biographical sources make it clear that Everett believed in the literal reality of the other quantum worlds.<ref name="MAD">Peter Byrne, [http://www.amazon.co.uk/dp/0199552274 The Many Worlds of Hugh Everett III: Multiple Universes, Mutual Assured Destruction, and the Meltdown of a Nuclear Family], ISBN 978-0-19-955227-6</ref> Everett's son reported that Hugh Everett "never wavered in his belief over his many-worlds theory".<ref name="newsciMark">{{Cite news | last = Aldhous | first = Peter | title = Parallel lives can never touch | magazine = New Scientist | issue = 2631 |date=2007-11-24 | url = http://www.newscientist.com/article/mg19626311.800-interview-parallel-lives-can-never-touch.html | accessdate = 2007-11-21 | postscript = <!--None--> }}</ref> Also Everett was reported to believe "his many-worlds theory guaranteed him [[Quantum suicide and immortality|immortality]]".<ref>[http://space.mit.edu/home/tegmark/everett/everett.html#e23 Eugene Shikhovtsev's Biography of Everett, in particular see "''Keith Lynch remembers 1979–1980''"]</ref>
| |
| | |
| One of MWI's strongest advocates is [[David Deutsch]].<ref name="deutsch98">[[David Deutsch]], ''The Fabric of Reality: The Science of Parallel Universes And Its Implications'', Penguin Books (1998), ISBN 0-14-027541-X</ref> According to Deutsch, the single photon interference pattern observed in the double slit experiment can be explained by interference of photons in multiple universes. Viewed in this way, the single photon interference experiment is indistinguishable from the multiple photon interference experiment. In a more practical vein, in one of the earliest papers on quantum computing,<ref name="deutsch85">[[David Deutsch]], Quantum theory, the Church–Turing principle and the universal quantum computer, ''Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A 400'', (1985), pp. 97–117</ref> he suggested that parallelism that results from the validity of MWI could lead to "''a method by which certain probabilistic tasks can be performed faster by a universal quantum computer than by any classical restriction of it''". Deutsch has also proposed that when reversible computers become conscious that MWI will be testable (at least against "naive" Copenhagenism) via the reversible observation of spin.<ref name="davis86">[[Paul C.W. Davies]], J.R. Brown, ''The Ghost in the Atom'' (1986) ISBN 0-521-31316-3, pp. 34–38: "The Many-Universes Interpretation", pp 83–105 for [[David Deutsch]]'s test of MWI and reversible quantum memories</ref>
| |
| | |
| [[Asher Peres]] was an outspoken critic of MWI; for example, a section in his 1993 textbook had the title ''Everett's interpretation and other bizarre theories''. In fact, Peres not only questioned whether MWI is really an "interpretation", but rather, if ''any'' interpretations of quantum mechanics are needed at all. Indeed, an interpretation can be regarded as a purely formal transformation, which adds nothing to the rules of the [[quantum mechanics]]. Peres seems to suggest that positing the existence of an infinite number of non-communicating [[Multiverse|parallel universes]] is highly suspect per those who interpret it as a violation of [[Occam's razor]], i.e., that it does not minimize the number of hypothesized entities. However, it is understood that the number of elementary particles are not a gross violation of Occam's Razor, one counts the types, not the tokens. [[Max Tegmark]] remarks that the alternative to many-worlds is "many words", an [[allusion]] to the complexity of [[von Neumann]]'s collapse postulate. On the other hand, the same derogatory qualification "many words" is often applied to MWI by its critics who see it as a word game which obfuscates rather than clarifies by confounding the von Neumann branching of possible worlds with the Schrödinger parallelism of many worlds in superposition.
| |
| | |
| MWI is considered by some to be [[unfalsifiable]] and hence unscientific because the multiple [[Multiverse|parallel universes]] are non-communicating, in the sense that no information can be passed between them. Others<ref name="davis86"/> claim MWI is directly testable. Everett regarded MWI as falsifiable since any test that falsifies conventional [[Quantum mechanics|quantum theory]] would also falsify MWI.<ref name="autogenerated2"/>
| |
| | |
| According to [[Martin Gardner]], the "other" worlds of MWI have two different interpretations: real or unreal, and claims that [[Stephen Hawking]] and [[Steve Weinberg]] both favour the unreal interpretation.<ref>[http://findarticles.com/p/articles/mi_m2843/is_3_26/ai_85932634 A response to Bryce DeWitt]{{Dead link|date=November 2009}}, Martin Gardner, May 2002</ref> Gardner also claims that the nonreal interpretation is favoured by the majority of physicists, whereas the "realist" view is only supported by MWI experts such as Deutsch and [[Bryce DeWitt]]. Hawking has said that "according to Feynman's idea", all the other histories are as "equally real" as our own,<ref name="hawkingreal">Award winning 1995 Channel 4 documentary "Reality on the rocks: Beyond our Ken" [http://www.windfallfilms.com/html/awards.htm] where, in response to [[Ken Campbell]]'s question "all these trillions of Universes of the Multiverse, are they as real as this one seems to be to me?" Hawking states, "Yes.... According to Feynman's idea, every possible history (of Ken) is equally real."</ref> and [[Martin Gardner]] reports Hawking saying that MWI is "trivially true".<ref>{{cite book | last = Gardner | first = Martin | authorlink = Martin Gardner | title = Are universes thicker than blackberries? | publisher = W.W. Norton | year = 2003 | isbn = 978-0-393-05742-3 | url = http://books.google.com/books?id=z9jH9mYiO5IC&pg=PA10&lpg=PA10 | page = 10 }}</ref> In a 1983 interview, Hawking also said he regarded the MWI as "self-evidently correct" but was dismissive towards questions about the interpretation of quantum mechanics, saying, "When I hear of [[Schrödinger's cat]], I reach for my gun." In the same interview, he also said, "But, look: All that one does, really, is to calculate conditional probabilities—in other words, the probability of A happening, given B. I think that that's all the many worlds interpretation is. Some people overlay it with a lot of mysticism about the wave function splitting into different parts. But all that you're calculating is conditional probabilities."<ref>{{cite book | last = Ferris | first = Timothy | authorlink = Timothy Ferris | title = The Whole Shebang | publisher = Simon & Schuster | year= 1997 | pages = [http://books.google.com/books?id=qjYbQ7EBAKwC&lpg=PP1&pg=PA345#v=onepage&q&f=false 345] | isbn = 978-0-684-81020-1 }}</ref> Elsewhere Hawking contrasted his attitude towards the "reality" of physical theories with that of his colleague [[Roger Penrose]], saying, "He's a [[Platonic realism|Platonist]] and I'm a [[Positivism|positivist]]. He's worried that Schrödinger's cat is in a quantum state, where it is half alive and half dead. He feels that can't correspond to reality. But that doesn't bother me. I don't demand that a theory correspond to reality because I don't know what it is. Reality is not a quality you can test with litmus paper. All I'm concerned with is that the theory should predict the results of measurements. Quantum theory does this very successfully."<ref>{{cite book | last = Hawking | first = Stephen | coauthors = Roger Penrose | title = The Nature of Space and Time | publisher = Princeton University Press | year= 1996 | pages = [http://books.google.com/books?id=LstaQTXP65cC&lpg=PP1&pg=PA121#v=onepage&q&f=false 121] | isbn = 978-0-691-03791-2 }}</ref> For his own part, Penrose agrees with Hawking that QM applied to the universe implies MW, although he considers the current lack of a successful theory of [[quantum gravity]] negates the claimed universality of conventional QM.<ref name="penrose">{{cite web | last = Penrose | first = Roger | authorlink = Roger Penrose | title = Roger Penrose Looks Beyond the Classic-Quantum Dichotomy | publisher = Sciencewatch |date=August 1991 | url = http://www.sciencewatch.com/interviews/roger_penrose2.htm | accessdate = 2007-10-21 }}</ref>
| |
| | |
| ===Polls===
| |
| | |
| Advocates of MWI often cite a poll of 72 "leading [[cosmologist]]s and other quantum field theorists"<ref>{{cite book |pages=35–36 |title= The Universe – Solved! |first= Jim |last= Elvridge. |isbn= 978-1-4243-3626-5 |date= 2008-01-02 |oclc= 247614399 |quote= 58% believed that the Many Worlds Interpretation (MWI) was true, including Stephen Hawking and Nobel Laureates [[Murray Gell-Mann]] and Richard Feynman }}</ref> conducted by the American political scientist David Raub in 1995 showing 58% agreement with "Yes, I think MWI is true".<ref>{{cite book |quote= [the poll was] published in the French periodical ''Sciences et Avenir'' in January 1998 |page= 33 |title= Beyond the bleep : the definitive unauthorized guide to What the bleep do we know!? |first= Alexandra |last= Bruce. |isbn= 978-1-932857-22-1 |chapter= How does reality work? }}</ref>
| |
| | |
| The poll is controversial: for example, [[Victor J. Stenger]] remarks that [[Murray Gell-Mann]]'s published work explicitly rejects the existence of simultaneous parallel universes. Collaborating with [[James Hartle]], Gell-Mann is working toward the development a more "palatable" ''post-Everett quantum mechanics''. Stenger thinks it's fair to say that most physicists dismiss the many-world interpretation as too extreme, while noting it "has merit in finding a place for the observer inside the system being analyzed and doing away with the troublesome notion of wave function collapse".<ref name="stenger1995">{{cite book |first=V.J. |last=Stenger |year=1995 |title=The Unconscious Quantum: Metaphysics in Modern Physics and Cosmology |publisher=Prometheus Books |isbn=978-1-57392-022-3 |lccn=lc95032599 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=1ZbvAAAAMAAJ |page=176 |quote=Gell-Man and collaborator James Hartle, along with a score of others, have been working to develop a more palatable interpretation of quantum mechanics that is free of the problems that plague all the interpretations we have considered so far. This new interpretation is called, in its various incarnations, '''post-Everett quantum mechanics''', alternate histories, consistent histories, or decoherent histories. I will not be overly concerned with the detailed differences between these characterizations and will use the terms more or less interchangeably.}}</ref>
| |
| | |
| [[Max Tegmark]] also reports the result of a "highly unscientific" poll taken at a 1997 quantum mechanics workshop.<ref>[http://space.mit.edu/home/tegmark/quantum.html Max Tegmark on many-worlds (contains MWI poll)]</ref> According to Tegmark, "The many worlds interpretation (MWI) scored second, comfortably ahead of the [[consistent histories]] and [[Bohm interpretation|Bohm interpretations]]." Such polls have been taken at other conferences, for example, in response to [[Sean M. Carroll|Sean Carroll]]'s observation, "As crazy as it sounds, most working physicists buy into the many-worlds theory"<ref>{{cite web |url=http://preposterousuniverse.blogspot.com/2004_04_01_preposterousuniverse_archive.html#108087902367974365 |archiveurl=http://web.archive.org/web/20040908014703/http://preposterousuniverse.blogspot.com/2004_04_01_preposterousuniverse_archive.html#108087902367974365 |archivedate=2004-09-08 |first=Sean |last=Caroll |title=Preposterous Universe |date=1 April 2004 |archivedate=8 September 2004}}</ref> [[Michael Nielsen]] counters: "at a quantum computing conference at Cambridge in 1998, a many-worlder surveyed the audience of approximately 200 people... Many-worlds did just fine, garnering support on a level comparable to, but somewhat below, Copenhagen and decoherence." However, Nielsen notes that it seemed most attendees found it to be a waste of time: [[Asher Peres]] "got a huge and sustained round of applause… when he got up at the end of the polling and asked ‘And who here believes the laws of physics are decided by a democratic vote?’"<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.qinfo.org/people/nielsen/blog/archive/000060.html |archiveurl=http://web.archive.org/web/20040520222807/http://www.qinfo.org/people/nielsen/blog/archive/000060.html |archivedate=2004-05-20 |first=Michael |last=Nielsen |title=Michael Nielsen: The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics |archivedate=20 May 2004 |date=3 April 2004}}</ref>
| |
| | |
| A 2005 poll of fewer than 40 students and researchers taken after a course on the Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics at the Institute for Quantum Computing University of Waterloo found "Many Worlds (and decoherence)" to be the least favored.<ref>[http://www.iqc.ca/~qipcourse/interpret/survey.html Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics class survey<!-- Bot generated title -->]</ref>
| |
| | |
| A 2011 poll of 33 participants at an Austrian conference found 6 endorsed MWI, 8 "Information-based/information-theoretical", and 14 Copenhagen;<ref>[http://arxiv.org/abs/1301.1069 "A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics"], Schlosshauer et al 2013</ref> the authors remark that the results are similar to Tegmark's 1998 poll.
| |
| | |
| ==Speculative implications==
| |
| Speculative physics deals with questions which are also discussed in science fiction.
| |
| | |
| ===Quantum suicide thought experiment===
| |
| {{main|Quantum suicide and immortality}}
| |
| '''Quantum suicide''', as a [[thought experiment]], was published independently by [[Hans Moravec]] in 1987<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.thestargarden.co.uk/ManyMinds.html |title=The Many Minds Approach |date=25 October 2010 |accessdate=7 December 2010 |quote=This idea was first proposed by Austrian mathematician Hans Moravec in 1987...}}</ref><ref name="Moravec1987">{{cite book |last=Moravec |first=Hans |year=1988 |title=Mind Children: The Future of Robot and Human Intelligence |chapter=The Doomsday Device |publisher=[[Harvard University Press]] |location=Harvard |page=188 |isbn=978-0-674-57618-6 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=56mb7XuSx3QC&lpg=PP188&pg=PA188}} (If MWI is true, apocalyptic particle accelerators won't function as advertised).</ref> and [[Bruno Marchal]] in 1988<ref name="Marchal1988">{{cite journal |last=Marchal |first=Bruno |year=1988 |title=Informatique théorique et philosophie de l'esprit |journal=Acte du 3ème colloque international Cognition et Connaissance [Proceedings of the 3rd International Conference Cognition and Knowledge] |location=Toulouse |pages=193–227 |trans_title=Theoretical Computer Science and Philosophy of Mind}}</ref><ref name="Marchal1991">{{cite journal |last=Marchal |first=Bruno |year=1991 |title=Mechanism and personal identity |editor1-last=De Glas |editor1-first=M. |editor2-last=Gabbay |editor2-first=D. |journal=Proceedings of WOCFAI 91 |pages=335–345 |location=Paris. Angkor. |url=http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/publications/M&PI_15-MAI-91.pdf}}</ref> and was independently developed further by [[Max Tegmark]] in 1998.<ref>Tegmark, Max [http://www.arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9709032/ The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Many Worlds or Many Words?], 1998</ref> It attempts to distinguish between the [[Copenhagen interpretation]] of quantum mechanics and the [[Everett many-worlds interpretation]] by means of a variation of the [[Schrödinger's cat]] [[thought experiment]], from the cat's point of view. '''Quantum immortality''' refers to the subjective experience of surviving quantum suicide regardless of the odds.<ref name="mit_edu">{{cite web |last=Tegmark |first=Max |title=Quantum immortality |url=http://space.mit.edu/home/tegmark/quantum.html#immortality |date=November 1998 |accessdate=25 October 2010}}</ref>
| |
| | |
| ===Weak coupling===
| |
| Another speculation is that the separate worlds remain weakly coupled (e.g., by gravity) permitting "communication between parallel universes". A possible test of this using quantum-optical equipment is described in a 1997 ''[[Foundations of Physics]]'' article by [[Rainer Plaga]].<ref name="plaga"/> It involves an isolated [[ion]] in an [[ion trap]], a quantum measurement that would yield two parallel worlds (their difference just being in the detection of a single photon), and the [[excitation]] of the ion from only one of these worlds. If the excited ion can be detected from the other parallel universe, then this would constitute direct evidence in support of the many-worlds interpretation and would automatically exclude the orthodox, "logical", and "many-histories" interpretations. The reason the ion is isolated is to make it not participate immediately in the decoherence which insulates the parallel world branches, therefore allowing it to act as a gateway between the two worlds, and if the measure apparatus could perform the measurements quickly enough before the gateway ion is decoupled then the test would succeed (with electronic computers the necessary time window between the two worlds would be in a time scale of [[millisecond]]s or [[nanosecond]]s, and if the measurements are taken by humans then a few seconds would still be enough). R. Plaga shows that macroscopic decoherence timescales are a possibility. The proposed test is based on technical equipment described in a 1993 ''[[Physical Review]]'' article by Itano et al.<ref name="itano">W.M.Itano et al., Phys.Rev. A47,3354 (1993).</ref> and R. Plaga says that this level of technology is enough to realize the proposed inter-world communication experiment. The necessary technology for precision measurements of single ions already exists since the 1970s, and the ion recommended for excitation is <sup>199</sup>Hg<sup>+</sup>. The excitation methodology is described by Itano et al. and the time needed for it is given by the [[Rabi flopping]] formula<ref>M.SargentIII,M.O.Scully and W.E.Lamb, Laser physics (Addison-Wesley, Reading, 1974), p.27.</ref>
| |
| | |
| Such a test as described by R. Plaga would mean that energy transfer is possible between parallel worlds. This does not violate the fundamental principles of physics because these require energy conservation only for the whole universe and not for the single parallel branches.<ref name="plaga" /> Neither the excitation of the single ion (which is a [[Degrees of freedom (physics and chemistry)|degree of freedom]] of the proposed system) leads to decoherence, something which is proven by [[Welcher Weg]] detectors which can excite atoms without momentum transfer (which causes the loss of coherence).<ref>M.O.Scully and H.Walther, Phys.Rev. A39,5229 (1989).</ref>
| |
| | |
| The proposed test would allow for low-bandwidth inter-world communication, the limiting factors of bandwidth and time being dependent on the technology of the equipment. Because of the time needed to determine the state of the partially decohered isolated excited ion based on Itano et al.'s methodology, the ion would decohere by the time its state is determined during the experiment, so Plaga's proposal would pass just enough information between the two worlds to confirm their parallel existence and nothing more. The author contemplates that with increased bandwidth, one could even transfer television imagery across the parallel worlds.<ref name="plaga" /> For example, Itano et al.'s methodology could be improved (by lowering the time needed for state determination of the excited ion) if a more efficient process were found for the detection of fluorescence radiation using 194 nm photons.<ref name="plaga" />
| |
| | |
| A 1991 article by J.Polchinski also supports the view that inter-world communication is a theoretical possibility.<ref>J.Polchinski, Phys.Rev.Lett. 66,397 (1991).</ref> Other authors in a 1994 preprint article also contemplated similar ideas.<ref>M.Gell-Mann and J.B.Hartle, Equivalent Sets of Histories and Multiple Quasiclassical Domains, preprint University of California at Santa Barbara UCSBTH-94-09 (1994).</ref>
| |
| | |
| The reason inter-world communication seems like a possibility is because [[decoherence]] which separates the parallel worlds is never fully complete,<ref name="zeh16">H.D.Zeh, Found.Phys. 3,109 (1973).</ref><ref>H.D.Zeh, Phys.Lett.A 172,189 (1993).</ref> therefore weak influences from one parallel world to another can still pass between them,<ref name="zeh16" /><ref>A.Albrecht, Phys.Rev. D48,3768 (1993).</ref> and these should be measurable with advanced technology. Deutsch proposed such an experiment in a 1985 ''[[International Journal of Theoretical Physics]]'' article,<ref>D.Deutsch, Int.J.theor.Phys. 24,1 (1985).</ref> but the technology it requires involves human-level [[artificial intelligence]].<ref name="plaga" />
| |
| | |
| ===Similarity to modal realism===
| |
| The many-worlds interpretation has some similarity to [[modal realism]] in [[philosophy]], which is the view that the [[possible world]]s used to interpret modal claims exist and are of a kind with the actual world. Unlike the possible worlds of philosophy, however, in quantum mechanics counterfactual alternatives can influence the results of experiments, as in the [[Elitzur–Vaidman bomb-testing problem]] or the [[Quantum Zeno effect]]. Also, while the worlds of the many-worlds interpretation all share the same physical laws, modal realism postulates a world for every way things could conceivably have been.
| |
| | |
| ===Time travel===
| |
| The many-worlds interpretation could be one possible way to resolve the paradoxes <ref name="deutsch98">[[David Deutsch]], ''The Fabric of Reality: The Science of Parallel Universes And Its Implications'', Penguin Books (1998), Chapter 12, ISBN 0-14-027541-X</ref> that one would expect to arise ''if'' [[time travel]] turns out to be permitted by physics (permitting [[closed timelike curves]] and thus violating [[causality]]). Entering the past would itself be a quantum event causing branching, and therefore the timeline accessed by the time traveller simply would be another timeline of many. In that sense, it would make the [[Novikov self-consistency principle]] unnecessary.
| |
| | |
| ==Many-worlds in literature and science fiction==
| |
| [[Image:Sobel North America.gif|thumb|right|250px|A map from [[Robert Sobel]]'s novel ''[[For Want of a Nail (novel)|For Want of a Nail]]'', an artistic illustration of how small events – in this example the branching or [[point of divergence]] from our timeline's history is in [[Saratoga campaign|October 1777]] – can profoundly alter the course of history. According to the many-worlds interpretation every event, even microscopic, is a branch point; all possible [[Alternate history|alternative histories]] actually exist.<ref name=dewitt71/>]]
| |
| {{Main|Parallel universe (fiction)}}
| |
| {{See also|Alternate History}}
| |
| | |
| The many-worlds interpretation (and the somewhat related concept of [[possible worlds]]) has been associated to numerous themes in [[literature]], [[art]] and [[science fiction]].
| |
| | |
| Some of these stories or films violate fundamental principles of causality and relativity, and are extremely misleading since the [[information theory|information-theoretic]] structure of the path space of multiple universes (that is information flow between different paths) is very likely extraordinarily complex. Also see [http://www.hedweb.com/manworld.htm Michael Clive Price's FAQ] referenced in the external links section below where these issues (and other similar ones) are dealt with more decisively.
| |
| | |
| Another kind of popular illustration of many-worlds splittings, which does not involve information flow between paths, or information flow backwards in time considers alternate outcomes of historical events. According to the many-worlds interpretation, all of the historical speculations entertained within the [[alternate history]] genre are realized in parallel universes.<ref name=dewitt71/>
| |
| | |
| The many-worlds interpretation of reality was anticipated with remarkable fidelity in [[Olaf Stapledon|Olaf Stapledon’s]] 1937 science fiction novel [[Star Maker]], in a paragraph describing one of the many universes created by the Star Maker god of the title. "In one inconceivable complex cosmos, whenever a creature was faced with several possible courses of action, it took them all, thereby creating many distinct temporal dimensions and distinct histories of the cosmos. Since in every evolutionary sequence of the cosmos there were very many creatures, and each was constantly faced with many possible courses, and the combinations of all their courses were innumerable, an infinity of distinct universes exfoliated from every moment of every temporal sequence in this cosmos."
| |
| | |
| ==See also==
| |
| {{cmn|2|
| |
| * [[Consistent histories]]
| |
| * [[EPR paradox]]
| |
| * ''[[Fabric of Reality]]''
| |
| * [[Garden of Forking Paths]]
| |
| * [[Interpretations of quantum mechanics]]
| |
| * [[Many-minds interpretation]]
| |
| * [[Multiverse]]
| |
| * [[Multiple histories]]
| |
| * ''[[The Beginning of Infinity]]''
| |
| * [[Quantum immortality]] – a thought experiment.
| |
| * [[Wave function collapse]]
| |
| }}
| |
| | |
| ==Notes==
| |
| {{reflist|colwidth=30em}}
| |
| | |
| ==Further reading==
| |
| * [[Jeffrey A. Barrett]], ''The Quantum Mechanics of Minds and Worlds'', Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1999.
| |
| * Peter Byrne, ''The Many Worlds of Hugh Everett III: Multiple Universes, Mutual Assured Destruction, and the Meltdown of a Nuclear Family'', Oxford University Press, 2010.
| |
| * Jeffrey A. Barrett and Peter Byrne, eds., "The Everett Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Collected Works 1955–1980 with Commentary", Princeton University Press, 2012.
| |
| * [[Julian Brown]], ''Minds, Machines, and the Multiverse'', Simon & Schuster, 2000, ISBN 0-684-81481-1
| |
| * [[Paul C.W. Davies]], ''Other Worlds'', (1980) ISBN 0-460-04400-1
| |
| * [[James P. Hogan (writer)|James P. Hogan]], ''The Proteus Operation'' (science fiction involving the many-worlds interpretation, time travel and World War 2 history), Baen, Reissue edition (August 1, 1996) ISBN 0-671-87757-7
| |
| * [[Adrian Kent]], [http://arxiv.org/abs/0905.0624 One world versus many: the inadequacy of Everettian accounts of evolution, probability, and scientific confirmation] * [[Asher Peres]], ''Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods'', Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1993.
| |
| * [[Andrei Linde]] and [[Vitaly Vanchurin]], [http://arxiv.org/abs/0910.1589v1 How Many Universes are in the Multiverse?]
| |
| * Stefano Osnaghi, Fabio Freitas, Olival Freire Jr, [http://stefano.osnaghi.free.fr/Everett.pdf The Origin of the Everettian Heresy], ''Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics'' 40(2009)97–123. A study of the painful three-way relationship between [[Hugh Everett]], [[John A Wheeler]] and [[Niels Bohr]] and how this affected the early development of the many-worlds theory.
| |
| * [[Mark A. Rubin]], Locality in the Everett Interpretation of Heisenberg-Picture Quantum Mechanics, ''Foundations of Physics Letters'', 14, (2001), pp. 301–322, {{arxiv|quant-ph/0103079}}
| |
| * [[David Wallace]]{{disambiguation needed|date=December 2012}}, [[Harvey Brown (philosopher)|Harvey R. Brown]], Solving the measurement problem: de Broglie–Bohm loses out to Everett, ''Foundations of Physics'', {{arxiv|quant-ph/0403094}}
| |
| * David Wallace, Worlds in the Everett Interpretation, ''Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics'', 33, (2002), pp. 637–661, {{arxiv|quant-ph/0103092}}
| |
| * [[John A. Wheeler]] and [[Wojciech Hubert Zurek]] (eds), ''Quantum Theory and Measurement'', [[Princeton University Press]], (1983), ISBN 0-691-08316-9
| |
| | |
| ==External links==
| |
| {{Sister project links| Many-worlds interpretation}}
| |
| * [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-everett/ Everett's Relative-State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics] – [[Jeffrey A. Barrett]]'s article on Everett's formulation of quantum mechanics in the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]].
| |
| * [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-manyworlds/ Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics] – [[Lev Vaidman]]'s article on the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics in the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]].
| |
| * [http://ucispace.lib.uci.edu/handle/10575/1060 Hugh Everett III Manuscript Archive (UC Irvine)] – [[Jeffrey A. Barrett]], Peter Byrne, and James O. Weatherall (eds.).
| |
| * [http://www.hedweb.com/manworld.htm Michael C Price's Everett FAQ] – a clear FAQ-style presentation of the theory.
| |
| * [http://frombob.to/many.html The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics] – a description for the lay reader with links.
| |
| * [http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9703089 Against Many-Worlds Interpretations by Adrian Kent]
| |
| * [http://www.mth.kcl.ac.uk/~streater/lostcauses.html#XII Many-Worlds is a "lost cause"] according to [[Ray Streater|R. F. Streater]]
| |
| * [http://www.johnsankey.ca/qm.html The many worlds of quantum mechanics] John Sankey
| |
| * [http://space.mit.edu/home/tegmark/quantum.html Max Tegmark's web page]
| |
| * [http://www-physics.lbl.gov/~stapp/bp.PDF Henry Stapp's critique of MWI, focusing on the basis problem] Canadian J. Phys. 80,1043–1052 (2002).
| |
| * [http://xstructure.inr.ac.ru/x-bin/theme2.py?arxiv=quant-ph&level=1&index1=5693 Everett hit count on arxiv.org]
| |
| * [http://users.ox.ac.uk/~everett/abstracts.htm Many Worlds 50th anniversary conference at Oxford]
| |
| * [http://www.perimeterinstitute.ca/en/Events/Many_Worlds_at_50/Many_Worlds_at_50/ "Many Worlds at 50" conference] at [[Perimeter Institute]]
| |
| * [http://www.scientificamerican.com/blog/post.cfm?id=many-worlds-in-oxford Scientific American report on the Many Worlds 50th anniversary conference at Oxford]
| |
| * {{Cite journal | last=Highfield | first=Roger| title=Parallel universe proof boosts time travel hopes | publisher = The Daily Telegraph | date=September 21, 2007 | url=http://www.telegraph.co.uk/earth/main.jhtml?xml=/earth/2007/09/21/sciuni121.xml | accessdate = 2007-10-26 | postscript=<!--None--> |archiveurl = http://web.archive.org/web/20071020024203/http://www.telegraph.co.uk/earth/main.jhtml?xml=/earth/2007/09/21/sciuni121.xml <!-- Bot retrieved archive --> |archivedate = 2007-10-20}}.
| |
| * [http://science.howstuffworks.com/quantum-suicide2.htm HowStuffWorks article]
| |
| * [http://www.physorg.com/news174921612.html Physicists Calculate Number of Parallel Universes] Physorg.com October 16, 2009.
| |
| * [http://www.youtube.com/user/TEDEducation?feature=watch TED-Education video] – [http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=a1bWKZFP2Tc&feature=relmfu How many universes are there?].
| |
| | |
| {{Time travel}}
| |
| | |
| {{DEFAULTSORT:Many-Worlds Interpretation}}
| |
| [[Category:Interpretations of quantum mechanics]]
| |
| [[Category:Quantum measurement]]
| |
| [[Category:Parallel universes (fiction)]]
| |
| [[Category:Reality]]
| |