|
|
Line 1: |
Line 1: |
| {{Bayesian statistics}}
| | Hello. Allow me introduce the author. Her name is Emilia Shroyer but it's not the most feminine title out there. Managing individuals is what I do and the salary has been really satisfying. Playing baseball is the hobby he will by no means quit doing. Minnesota is where he's been living for years.<br><br>my blog ... at home std test ([http://www.mycamspy.com/blog/64881 Going in www.mycamspy.com]) |
| In [[statistics]], '''Bayesian inference''' is a method of [[statistical inference|inference]] in which [[Bayes' rule]] is used to update the probability estimate for a hypothesis as additional [[evidence]] is acquired. Bayesian updating is an important technique throughout statistics, and especially in [[mathematical statistics]]. For some cases, exhibiting a Bayesian derivation for a statistical method automatically ensures that the method works as well as any competing method.
| |
| {{Citation needed|date=July 2013}}
| |
| Bayesian updating is especially important in the [[Sequential analysis|dynamic analysis of a sequence of data]]. Bayesian inference has found application in a range of fields including [[science]], [[engineering]], [[philosophy]], [[medicine]] and [[law]].
| |
| | |
| In the philosophy of [[decision theory]], Bayesian inference is closely related to discussions of subjective probability, often called "[[Bayesian probability]]". [[Bayesian probability]] provides a [[Rationality|rational]] method for updating beliefs.
| |
| <!--
| |
| ; however, non-Bayesian updating rules are compatible with rationality, according to philosophers [[Ian Hacking]] and [[Bas van Fraassen]].<ref>Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy; Bayesian Epistemology; http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-bayesian</ref><ref>Gillies, Donald (2000); "Philosophical Theories of Probability"; Routledge; Chapter 4 "The subjective theory"</ref>
| |
| -->
| |
| | |
| ==Introduction to Bayes' rule==
| |
| {{Main|Bayes' rule}}
| |
| {{See also|Bayesian probability}}
| |
| | |
| ===Formal===
| |
| Bayesian inference derives the [[posterior probability]] as a [[consequence relation|consequence]] of two [[Antecedent (logic)|antecedent]]s, a [[prior probability]] and a "[[likelihood function]]" derived from a probability model for the data to be observed. Bayesian inference computes the posterior probability according to [[Bayes' rule]]:
| |
| :<math>P(H|E) = \frac{P(E|H) \cdot P(H)}{P(E)}</math>
| |
| where
| |
| * <math>\textstyle |</math> means ''given''.
| |
| * <math>\textstyle H</math> stands for any ''hypothesis'' whose probability may be affected by [[Experimental data|data]] (called ''evidence'' below). Often there are competing hypotheses, from which one chooses the most probable.
| |
| * the ''evidence'' <math>\textstyle E</math> corresponds to new data that were not used in computing the prior probability.
| |
| * <math>\textstyle P(H)</math>, the ''[[prior probability]]'', is the probability of <math>\textstyle H</math> ''before'' <math>\textstyle E</math> is observed. This indicates one's previous estimate of the probability that a hypothesis is true, before gaining the current evidence.
| |
| * <math>\textstyle P(H|E)</math>, the ''[[posterior probability]]'', is the probability of <math>\textstyle H</math> ''given'' <math>\textstyle E</math>, i.e., ''after'' <math>\textstyle E</math> is observed. This tells us what we want to know: the probability of a hypothesis ''given'' the observed evidence.
| |
| * <math>\textstyle P(E|H)</math>, the probability of observing <math>\textstyle E</math> ''given'' <math>\textstyle H</math>, is also known as the ''[[Likelihood function|likelihood]]''. It indicates the compatibility of the evidence with the given hypothesis.
| |
| * <math>\textstyle P(E)</math> is sometimes termed the [[marginal likelihood]] or "model evidence". This factor is the same for all possible hypotheses being considered. (This can be seen by the fact that the hypothesis <math>\textstyle H</math> does not appear anywhere in the symbol, unlike for all the other factors.) This means that this factor does not enter into determining the relative probabilities of different hypotheses.
| |
| | |
| Note that what affect the value of <math>\textstyle P(H|E)</math> for different values of <math>\textstyle H</math> are only the factors <math>\textstyle P(H)</math> and <math>\textstyle P(E|H)</math>, which both appear in the numerator, and hence the posterior probability is proportional to both. In words:
| |
| * (more exactly) ''The posterior probability of a hypothesis is determined by a combination of the inherent likeliness of a hypothesis (the prior) and the compatibility of the observed evidence with the hypothesis (the likelihood).''
| |
| * (more concisely) ''Posterior is proportional to likelihood times prior.''
| |
| | |
| Note that Bayes' rule can also be written as follows:
| |
| :<math>P(H|E) = \frac{P(E|H)}{P(E)} \cdot P(H)</math>
| |
| where the factor <math>\textstyle \frac{P(E|H)}{P(E)}</math> represents the impact of <math>E</math> on the probability of <math>H</math>.
| |
| | |
| ===Informal===
| |
| | |
| Rationally, Bayes' rule makes a great deal of sense. If the evidence does not match up with a hypothesis, one should reject the hypothesis. But if a hypothesis is extremely unlikely ''a priori'', one should also reject it, even if the evidence does appear to match up.
| |
| | |
| For example, imagine that I have various hypotheses about the nature of a newborn baby of a friend, including:
| |
| * <math>\textstyle H_1</math>: the baby is a brown-haired boy.
| |
| * <math>\textstyle H_2</math>: the baby is a blond-haired girl.
| |
| * <math>\textstyle H_3</math>: the baby is a dog.
| |
| Then consider two scenarios:
| |
| # I'm presented with evidence in the form of a picture of a blond-haired baby girl. I find this evidence supports <math>\textstyle H_2</math> and opposes <math>\textstyle H_1</math> and <math>\textstyle H_3</math>.
| |
| # I'm presented with evidence in the form of a picture of a baby dog. Although this evidence, treated in isolation, supports <math>\textstyle H_3</math>, my prior belief in this hypothesis (that a human can give birth to a dog) is extremely small, so the posterior probability is nevertheless small.
| |
| | |
| The critical point about Bayesian inference, then, is that it provides a principled way of combining new evidence with prior beliefs, through the application of Bayes' rule. (Contrast this with frequentist inference, which relies only on the evidence as a whole, with no reference to prior beliefs.) Furthermore, Bayes' rule can be applied iteratively: after observing some evidence, the resulting posterior probability can then be treated as a prior probability, and a new posterior probability computed from new evidence. This allows for Bayesian principles to be applied to various kinds of evidence, whether viewed all at once or over time. This procedure is termed "Bayesian updating".
| |
| | |
| ===Bayesian updating===
| |
| Bayesian updating is widely used and computationally convenient. However, it is not the only updating rule that might be considered "rational".
| |
| | |
| [[Ian Hacking]] noted that traditional "[[Dutch book]]" arguments did not specify Bayesian updating: they left open the possibility that non-Bayesian updating rules could avoid Dutch books. [[Ian Hacking|Hacking]] wrote<ref>Hacking (1967, Section 3, p. 316), Hacking (1988, p. 124)</ref> "And neither the Dutch book argument, nor any other in the personalist arsenal of proofs of the probability axioms, entails the dynamic assumption. Not one entails Bayesianism. So the personalist requires the dynamic assumption to be Bayesian. It is true that in consistency a personalist could abandon the Bayesian model of learning from experience. [[Salt and Light|Salt could lose its savour]]."
| |
| | |
| Indeed, there are non-Bayesian updating rules that also avoid Dutch books (as discussed in the literature on "[[probability kinematics]]" following the publication of [[Richard C. Jeffrey]]'s rule, which applies Bayes' rule to the case where the evidence itself is assigned a probability.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/bayes-theorem/ |title=Bayes' Theorem (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) |publisher=Plato.stanford.edu |date= |accessdate=2014-01-05}}</ref> The additional hypotheses needed to uniquely require Bayesian updating have been deemed to be substantial, complicated, and unsatisfactory.<ref>[[Bas van Fraassen|van Fraassen, B.]] (1989) ''Laws and Symmetry'', Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-824860-1</ref>
| |
| | |
| ==Formal description of Bayesian inference==
| |
| | |
| ===Definitions===
| |
| *<math>x</math>, a data point in general. This may in fact be a [[random vector|vector]] of values.
| |
| *<math>\theta</math>, the [[parameter]] of the data point's distribution, i.e., <math>x \sim p(x|\theta)</math> . This may in fact be a [[random vector|vector]] of parameters.
| |
| *<math>\alpha</math>, the [[hyperparameter]] of the parameter, i.e., <math>\theta \sim p(\theta|\alpha)</math> . This may in fact be a [[random vector|vector]] of hyperparameters.
| |
| *<math>\mathbf{X}</math>, a set of <math>n</math> observed data points, i.e., <math>x_1,\ldots,x_n</math> .
| |
| *<math>\tilde{x}</math>, a new data point whose distribution is to be predicted.
| |
| | |
| ===Bayesian inference===
| |
| | |
| *The [[prior distribution]] is the distribution of the parameter(s) before any data is observed, i.e. <math>p(\theta|\alpha)</math> .
| |
| *The prior distribution might not be easily determined. In this case, we can use the [[Jeffreys prior]] to obtain the posterior distribution before updating them with newer observations.
| |
| | |
| *The [[sampling distribution]] is the distribution of the observed data conditional on its parameters, i.e. <math>p(\mathbf{X}|\theta)</math> . This is also termed the [[likelihood function|likelihood]], especially when viewed as a function of the parameter(s), sometimes written <math>\operatorname{L}(\theta;\mathbf{X}) = p(\mathbf{X}|\theta)</math> .
| |
| *The [[marginal likelihood]] (sometimes also termed the ''evidence'') is the distribution of the observed data [[marginal distribution|marginalized]] over the parameter(s), i.e. <math>p(\mathbf{X}|\alpha) = \int_{\theta} p(\mathbf{X}|\theta) p(\theta|\alpha) \operatorname{d}\!\theta</math> .
| |
| *The [[posterior distribution]] is the distribution of the parameter(s) after taking into account the observed data. This is determined by [[Bayes' rule]], which forms the heart of Bayesian inference:
| |
| :<math>p(\theta|\mathbf{X},\alpha) = \frac{p(\mathbf{X}|\theta) p(\theta|\alpha)}{p(\mathbf{X}|\alpha)} \propto p(\mathbf{X}|\theta) p(\theta|\alpha)</math>
| |
| | |
| Note that this is expressed in words as "posterior is proportional to likelihood times prior", or sometimes as "posterior = likelihood times prior, over evidence".
| |
| | |
| ===Bayesian prediction===
| |
| | |
| *The [[posterior predictive distribution]] is the distribution of a new data point, marginalized over the posterior:
| |
| :<math>p(\tilde{x}|\mathbf{X},\alpha) = \int_{\theta} p(\tilde{x}|\theta) p(\theta|\mathbf{X},\alpha) \operatorname{d}\!\theta</math>
| |
| *The [[prior predictive distribution]] is the distribution of a new data point, marginalized over the prior:
| |
| :<math>p(\tilde{x}|\alpha) = \int_{\theta} p(\tilde{x}|\theta) p(\theta|\alpha) \operatorname{d}\!\theta</math>
| |
| | |
| Bayesian theory calls for the use of the posterior predictive distribution to do [[predictive inference]], i.e., to [[prediction|predict]] the distribution of a new, unobserved data point. That is, instead of a fixed point as a prediction, a distribution over possible points is returned. Only this way is the entire posterior distribution of the parameter(s) used. By comparison, prediction in [[frequentist statistics]] often involves finding an optimum point estimate of the parameter(s)—e.g., by [[maximum likelihood]] or [[maximum a posteriori estimation]] (MAP)—and then plugging this estimate into the formula for the distribution of a data point. This has the disadvantage that it does not account for any uncertainty in the value of the parameter, and hence will underestimate the [[variance]] of the predictive distribution.
| |
| | |
| (In some instances, frequentist statistics can work around this problem. For example, [[confidence interval]]s and [[prediction interval]]s in frequentist statistics when constructed from a [[normal distribution]] with unknown [[mean]] and [[variance]] are constructed using a [[Student's t-distribution]]. This correctly estimates the variance, due to the fact that (1) the average of normally distributed random variables is also normally distributed; (2) the predictive distribution of a normally distributed data point with unknown mean and variance, using conjugate or uninformative priors, has a student's t-distribution. In Bayesian statistics, however, the posterior predictive distribution can always be determined exactly—or at least, to an arbitrary level of precision, when numerical methods are used.)
| |
| | |
| Note that both types of predictive distributions have the form of a [[compound probability distribution]] (as does the [[marginal likelihood]]). In fact, if the prior distribution is a [[conjugate prior]], and hence the prior and posterior distributions come from the same family, it can easily be seen that both prior and posterior predictive distributions also come from the same family of compound distributions. The only difference is that the posterior predictive distribution uses the updated values of the hyperparameters (applying the Bayesian update rules given in the [[conjugate prior]] article), while the prior predictive distribution uses the values of the hyperparameters that appear in the prior distribution.
| |
| | |
| ==Inference over exclusive and exhaustive possibilities==
| |
| If evidence is simultaneously used to update belief over a set of exclusive and exhaustive propositions, Bayesian inference may be thought of as acting on this belief distribution as a whole.
| |
| | |
| ===General formulation===
| |
| [[File:Bayesian inference event space.svg|thumb|Diagram illustrating event space <math>\Omega</math> in general formulation of Bayesian inference. Although this diagram shows discrete models and events, the continuous case may be visualized similarly using probability densities.]]
| |
| | |
| Suppose a process is generating independent and identically distributed events <math>E_n</math>, but the probability distribution is unknown. Let the event space <math>\Omega</math> represent the current state of belief for this process. Each model is represented by event <math>M_m</math>. The conditional probabilities <math>P(E_n|M_m)</math> are specified to define the models. <math>P(M_m)</math> is the degree of belief in <math>M_m</math>. Before the first inference step, <math>\{P(M_m)\}</math> is a set of ''initial prior probabilities''. These must sum to 1, but are otherwise arbitrary.
| |
| | |
| Suppose that the process is observed to generate <math>\textstyle E \in \{E_n\}</math>. For each <math>M \in \{M_m\}</math>, the prior <math>P(M)</math> is updated to the posterior <math>P(M|E)</math>. From [[Bayes' theorem]]:<ref>Gelman, Andrew; Carlin, John B.; Stern, Hal S.; Rubin, Donald B. (2003). ''Bayesian Data Analysis'', Second Edition. Boca Raton, FL: Chapman and Hall/CRC. ISBN 1-58488-388-X.</ref>
| |
| | |
| :<math>P(M|E) = \frac{P(E|M)}{\sum_m {P(E|M_m) P(M_m)}} \cdot P(M)</math>
| |
| | |
| Upon observation of further evidence, this procedure may be repeated.
| |
| | |
| ===Multiple observations===
| |
| | |
| For a set of [[independent and identically distributed]] observations <math>\mathbf{E} = \{e_1, \dots, e_n\}</math>, it may be shown that repeated application of the above is equivalent to
| |
| | |
| :<math>P(M|\mathbf{E}) = \frac{P(\mathbf{E}|M)}{\sum_m {P(\mathbf{E}|M_m) P(M_m)}} \cdot P(M)</math>
| |
| | |
| Where
| |
| | |
| :<math>P(\mathbf{E}|M) = \prod_k{P(e_k|M)}.</math>
| |
| | |
| This may be used to optimize practical calculations. <!-- It may be more informative if an actual example is given: e1/M, e2/M, ... might be shown as .05/4, .061/4, .033/4. Then showing the actual calculations using these three terms in the summation. -->
| |
| | |
| ===Parametric formulation===
| |
| | |
| By parametrizing the space of models, the belief in all models may be updated in a single step. The distribution of belief over the model space may then be thought of as a distribution of belief over the parameter space. The distributions in this section are expressed as continuous, represented by probability densities, as this is the usual situation. The technique is however equally applicable to discrete distributions.
| |
| | |
| Let the vector <math>\mathbf{\theta}</math> span the parameter space. Let the initial prior distribution over <math>\mathbf{\theta}</math> be <math>p(\mathbf{\theta}|\mathbf{\alpha})</math>, where <math>\mathbf{\alpha}</math> is a set of parameters to the prior itself, or ''[[hyperparameter]]s''. Let <math>\mathbf{E} = \{e_1, \dots, e_n\}</math> be a set of [[Independent and identically distributed random variables|independent and identically distributed]] event observations, where all <math>e_i</math> are distributed as <math>p(e|\mathbf{\theta})</math> for some <math>\mathbf{\theta}</math>. [[Bayes' theorem]] is applied to find the [[posterior distribution]] over <math>\mathbf{\theta}</math>:
| |
| | |
| :<math>
| |
| \begin{align}
| |
| p(\mathbf{\theta}|\mathbf{E},\mathbf{\alpha}) &= \frac{p(\mathbf{E}|\mathbf{\theta},\mathbf{\alpha})}{p(\mathbf{E}|\mathbf{\alpha})} \cdot p(\mathbf{\theta}|\mathbf{\alpha}) \\
| |
| &= \frac{p(\mathbf{E}|\mathbf{\theta},\mathbf{\alpha})}{\int_\mathbf{\theta} p(\mathbf{E}|\mathbf{\theta},\mathbf{\alpha}) p(\mathbf{\theta}|\mathbf{\alpha}) \, d\mathbf{\theta}} \cdot p(\mathbf{\theta}|\mathbf{\alpha})
| |
| \end{align}
| |
| </math>
| |
| | |
| Where
| |
| | |
| :<math>p(\mathbf{E}|\mathbf{\theta},\mathbf{\alpha}) = \prod_k p(e_k|\mathbf{\theta})</math>
| |
| | |
| ==Mathematical properties==
| |
| {{More footnotes|section|date=February 2012}}
| |
| | |
| ===Interpretation of factor===
| |
| | |
| <math>\textstyle \frac{P(E|M)}{P(E)} > 1 \Rightarrow \textstyle P(E|M) > P(E)</math>. That is, if the model were true, the evidence would be more likely than is predicted by the current state of belief. The reverse applies for a decrease in belief. If the belief does not change, <math>\textstyle \frac{P(E|M)}{P(E)} = 1 \Rightarrow \textstyle P(E|M) = P(E)</math>. That is, the evidence is independent of the model. If the model were true, the evidence would be exactly as likely as predicted by the current state of belief.
| |
| | |
| ===Cromwell's rule===
| |
| | |
| {{Main|Cromwell's rule}}
| |
| | |
| If <math>P(M)=0</math> then <math>P(M|E)=0</math>. If <math>P(M)=1</math>, then <math>P(M|E)=1</math>. This can be interpreted to mean that hard convictions are insensitive to counter-evidence.
| |
| | |
| The former follows directly from Bayes' theorem. The latter can be derived by applying the first rule to the event "not <math>M</math>" in place of "<math>M</math>", yielding "if <math>1 - P(M)=0</math>, then <math>1 - P(M|E)=0</math>", from which the result immediately follows.
| |
| | |
| ===Asymptotic behaviour of posterior===
| |
| | |
| Consider the behaviour of a belief distribution as it is updated a large number of times with [[independent and identically distributed]] trials. For sufficiently nice prior probabilities, the [[Bernstein–von Mises theorem|Bernstein-von Mises theorem]] gives that in the limit of infinite trials and the posterior converges to a [[Gaussian distribution]] independent of the initial prior under some conditions firstly outlined and rigorously proven by [[Joseph L. Doob]] in 1948, namely if the random variable in consideration has a finite [[probability space]]. The more general results were obtained later by the statistician [[David A. Freedman (statistician)|David A. Freedman]] who published in two seminal research papers{{Citation needed|date=February 2012}} in 1963 and 1965 when and under what circumstances the asymptotic behaviour of posterior is guaranteed. His 1963 paper treats, like Doob (1949), the finite case and comes to a satisfactory conclusion. However, if the random variable has an infinite but countable [[probability space]] (i.e., corresponding to a die with infinite many faces) the 1965 paper demonstrates that for a dense subset of priors the [[Bernstein–von Mises theorem|Bernstein-von Mises theorem]] is not applicable. In this case there is [[almost surely]] no asymptotic convergence. Later in the 1980s and 1990s [[David A. Freedman (statistician)|Freedman]] and [[Persi Diaconis]] continued to work on the case of infinite countable probability spaces.<ref>Larry Wasserman et alia, JASA 2000.</ref> To summarise, there may be insufficient trials to suppress the effects of the initial choice, and especially for large (but finite) systems the convergence might be very slow.
| |
| | |
| ===Conjugate priors===
| |
| {{Main|Conjugate prior}}
| |
| | |
| In parameterized form, the prior distribution is often assumed to come from a family of distributions called [[conjugate prior]]s. The usefulness of a conjugate prior is that the corresponding posterior distribution will be in the same family, and the calculation may be expressed in [[Closed-form expression|closed form]].
| |
| | |
| ===Estimates of parameters and predictions===
| |
| It is often desired to use a posterior distribution to estimate a parameter or variable. Several methods of Bayesian estimation select [[central tendency|measurements of central tendency]] from the posterior distribution.
| |
| | |
| For one-dimensional problems, a unique median exists for practical continuous problems. The posterior median is attractive as a [[robust statistics|robust estimator]].<ref>{{cite book|title=Pitman's measure of closeness: A comparison of statistical estimators|first=Pranab K.|last=Sen|authorlink1=Pranab K. Sen|first2=J. P.|last2=Keating|first3=R. L.|last3=Mason|publisher=SIAM|location=Philadelphia|year=1993|mr=|ref=harv}}</ref>
| |
| | |
| If there exists a finite mean for the posterior distribution, then the posterior mean is a method of estimation.{{citation needed|date=April 2013}}
| |
| :<math>\tilde \theta = \operatorname{E}[\theta] = \int_\theta \theta \, p(\theta|\mathbf{X},\alpha) \, d\theta</math>
| |
| | |
| Taking a value with the greatest probability defines [[maximum a posteriori estimation|maximum ''a posteriori'' (MAP)]] estimates:{{citation needed|date=April 2013}}
| |
| | |
| :<math>\{ \theta_{\text{MAP}}\} \subset \arg \max_\theta p(\theta|\mathbf{X},\alpha) .</math>
| |
| | |
| There are examples where no maximum is attained, in which case the set of MAP estimates is [[empty set|empty]].
| |
| | |
| There are other methods of estimation that minimize the posterior ''[[risk]]'' (expected-posterior loss) with respect to a [[loss function]], and these are of interest to [[statistical decision theory]] using the sampling distribution ("frequentist statistics").{{citation needed|date=April 2013}}
| |
| | |
| The [[posterior predictive distribution]] of a new observation <math>\tilde{x}</math> (that is independent of previous observations) is determined by{{citation needed|date=April 2013}}
| |
| | |
| :<math>p(\tilde{x}|\mathbf{X},\alpha) = \int_\theta p(\tilde{x},\theta|\mathbf{X},\alpha) \, d\theta = \int_\theta p(\tilde{x}|\theta) p(\theta|\mathbf{X},\alpha) \, d\theta .</math>
| |
| | |
| ==Examples==
| |
| | |
| ===Probability of a hypothesis===
| |
| | |
| Suppose there are two full bowls of cookies. Bowl #1 has 10 chocolate chip and 30 plain cookies, while bowl #2 has 20 of each. Our friend Fred picks a bowl at random, and then picks a cookie at random. We may assume there is no reason to believe Fred treats one bowl differently from another, likewise for the cookies. The cookie turns out to be a plain one. How probable is it that Fred picked it out of bowl #1?
| |
| | |
| Intuitively, it seems clear that the answer should be more than a half, since there are more plain cookies in bowl #1. The precise answer is given by Bayes' theorem. Let <math>H_1</math> correspond to bowl #1, and <math>H_2</math> to bowl #2.
| |
| It is given that the bowls are identical from Fred's point of view, thus <math>P(H_1)=P(H_2)</math>, and the two must add up to 1, so both are equal to 0.5.
| |
| The event <math>E</math> is the observation of a plain cookie. From the contents of the bowls, we know that <math>P(E|H_1) = 30/40 = 0.75</math> and <math>P(E|H_2) = 20/40 = 0.5</math>. Bayes' formula then yields
| |
| | |
| : <math>\begin{align} P(H_1|E) &= \frac{P(E|H_1)\,P(H_1)}{P(E|H_1)\,P(H_1)\;+\;P(E|H_2)\,P(H_2)} \\ \\ \ & = \frac{0.75 \times 0.5}{0.75 \times 0.5 + 0.5 \times 0.5} \\ \\ \ & = 0.6 \end{align}
| |
| </math>
| |
| | |
| Before we observed the cookie, the probability we assigned for Fred having chosen bowl #1 was the prior probability, <math>P(H_1)</math>, which was 0.5. After observing the cookie, we must revise the probability to <math>P(H_1|E)</math>, which is 0.6.
| |
| | |
| ===Making a prediction===
| |
| [[File:Bayesian inference archaeology example.jpg|thumb|Example results for archaeology example. This simulation was generated using c=15.2.]]
| |
| | |
| An archaeologist is working at a site thought to be from the medieval period, between the 11th century to the 16th century. However, it is uncertain exactly when in this period the site was inhabited. Fragments of pottery are found, some of which are glazed and some of which are decorated. It is expected that if the site were inhabited during the early medieval period, then 1% of the pottery would be glazed and 50% of its area decorated, whereas if it had been inhabited in the late medieval period then 81% would be glazed and 5% of its area decorated. How confident can the archaeologist be in the date of inhabitation as fragments are unearthed?
| |
| | |
| The degree of belief in the continuous variable <math>C</math> (century) is to be calculated, with the discrete set of events <math>\{GD,G \bar D, \bar G D, \bar G \bar D\}</math> as evidence. Assuming linear variation of glaze and decoration with time, and that these variables are independent,
| |
| | |
| :<math>P(E=GD|C=c) = (0.01 + 0.16(c-11))(0.5 - 0.09(c-11))</math>
| |
| :<math>P(E=G \bar D|C=c) = (0.01 + 0.16(c-11))(0.5 + 0.09(c-11))</math>
| |
| :<math>P(E=\bar G D|C=c) = (0.99 - 0.16(c-11))(0.5 - 0.09(c-11))</math>
| |
| :<math>P(E=\bar G \bar D|C=c) = (0.99 - 0.16(c-11))(0.5 + 0.09(c-11))</math>
| |
| | |
| Assume a uniform prior of <math>\textstyle f_C(c) = 0.2</math>, and that trials are [[independent and identically distributed]]. When a new fragment of type <math>e</math> is discovered, Bayes' theorem is applied to update the degree of belief for each <math>c</math>:
| |
| | |
| <math>f_C(c|E=e) = \frac{P(E=e|C=c)}{P(E=e)}f_C(c) = \frac{P(E=e|C=c)}{\int_{11}^{16}{P(E=e|C=c)f_C(c)dc}}f_C(c)</math>
| |
| | |
| A computer simulation of the changing belief as 50 fragments are unearthed is shown on the graph. In the simulation, the site was inhabited around 1520, or <math>c=15.2</math>. By calculating the area under the relevant portion of the graph for 50 trials, the archaeologist can say that there is practically no chance the site was inhabited in the 11th and 12th centuries, about 1% chance that it was inhabited during the 13th century, 63% chance during the 14th century and 36% during the 15th century. Note that the [[Bernstein–von Mises theorem|Bernstein-von Mises theorem]] asserts here the asymptotic convergence to the "true" distribution because the [[probability space]] corresponding to the discrete set of events <math>\{GD,G \bar D, \bar G D, \bar G \bar D\}</math> is finite (see above section on asymptotic behaviour of the posterior).
| |
| | |
| ==In frequentist statistics and decision theory==
| |
| | |
| A [[statistical decision theory|decision-theoretic]] justification of the use of Bayesian inference was given by [[Abraham Wald]], who proved that every Bayesian procedure is [[admissible decision rule|admissible]]. Conversely, every [[admissible decision rule|admissible]] statistical procedure is either a Bayesian procedure or a limit of Bayesian procedures.<ref name="Bickel & Doksum 2001, page 32">Bickel & Doksum (2001, p. 32)</ref>
| |
| | |
| Wald characterized admissible procedures as Bayesian procedures (and limits of Bayesian procedures), making the Bayesian formalism a central technique in such areas of [[frequentist inference]] as [[parameter estimation]], [[hypothesis testing]], and computing [[confidence intervals]].<ref>* {{cite journal
| |
| |doi=10.1214/aoms/1177700051|author=[[Jack Kiefer (mathematician)|Kiefer, J.]] and Schwartz, R.
| |
| |title=Admissible Bayes Character of T<sup>2</sup>-, R<sup>2</sup>-, and Other Fully Invariant Tests for Multivariate Normal Problems|journal=Annals of Mathematical Statistics| volume=36|year=1965|pages=747–770}}
| |
| * {{cite journal |doi= 10.1214/aoms/1177697822| author=Schwartz, R.|title=Invariant Proper Bayes Tests for Exponential Families |journal=Annals of Mathematical Statistics| volume=40 |year=1969| pages=270–283}}
| |
| * {{cite journal|doi=10.1214/aos/1176345877|author=Hwang, J. T. and Casella, George |title=Minimax Confidence Sets for the Mean of a Multivariate Normal Distribution|journal=Annals of Statistics| volume=10| pages=868–881|year=1982}}</ref> For example:
| |
| * "Under some conditions, all admissible procedures are either Bayes procedures or limits of Bayes procedures (in various senses). These remarkable results, at least in their original form, are due essentially to Wald. They are useful because the property of being Bayes is easier to analyze than admissibility."<ref name="Bickel & Doksum 2001, page 32"/>
| |
| | |
| * "In decision theory, a quite general method for proving admissibility consists in exhibiting a procedure as a unique Bayes solution."<ref>{{cite book|author=[[Erich Leo Lehmann|Lehmann, Erich]]| title=Testing Statistical Hypotheses|edition=Second|year=1986}} (see p. 309 of Chapter 6.7 "Admissibilty", and pp. 17–18 of Chapter 1.8 "Complete Classes"</ref>
| |
| | |
| *"In the first chapters of this work, prior distributions with finite support and the corresponding Bayes procedures were used to establish some of the main theorems relating to the comparison of experiments. Bayes procedures with respect to more general prior distributions have played a very important role in the development of statistics, including its asymptotic theory." "There are many problems where a glance at posterior distributions, for suitable priors, yields immediately interesting information. Also, this technique can hardly be avoided in sequential analysis."<ref>{{cite book
| |
| |author=[[Lucien Le Cam|Le Cam, Lucien]]
| |
| |title=Asymptotic Methods in Statistical Decision Theory|year=1986|publisher=Springer-Verlag
| |
| |isbn=0-387-96307-3}} (From "Chapter 12 Posterior Distributions and Bayes Solutions", p. 324)</ref>
| |
| | |
| *"A useful fact is that any Bayes decision rule obtained by taking a proper prior over the whole parameter space must be admissible"<ref>{{cite book
| |
| |author=[[David R. Cox|Cox, D. R.]] and Hinkley, D.V
| |
| |title=Theoretical Statistics
| |
| |year=1974
| |
| |publisher=Chapman and Hall
| |
| |isbn=0-04-121537-0
| |
| }} page 432
| |
| </ref>
| |
| *"An important area of investigation in the development of admissibility ideas has been that of conventional sampling-theory procedures, and many interesting results have been obtained."<ref>{{cite book|author=[[David R. Cox|Cox, D. R.]] and Hinkley, D. V. |title=Theoretical Statistics|year=1974 |publisher=Chapman and Hall|isbn=0-04-121537-0}} p. 433)</ref>
| |
| | |
| ===Model selection===
| |
| {{Hatnote|See [[Bayesian model selection]]}}
| |
| | |
| ==Applications==
| |
| | |
| ===Computer applications===
| |
| Bayesian inference has applications in [[artificial intelligence]] and [[expert system]]s. Bayesian inference techniques have been a fundamental part of computerized [[pattern recognition]] techniques since the late 1950s. There is also an ever growing connection between Bayesian methods and simulation-based [[Monte Carlo method|Monte Carlo]] techniques since complex models cannot be processed in closed form by a Bayesian analysis, while a [[graphical model]] structure ''may'' allow for efficient simulation algorithms like the [[Gibbs sampling]] and other [[Metropolis–Hastings algorithm]] schemes.<ref>{{cite book|author=Jim Albert|year=2009|title= Bayesian Computation with R, Second edition|publisher=Springer|location=New York, Dordrecht, etc.|isbn= 978-0-387-92297-3|ref=harv}}</ref> Recently Bayesian inference has gained popularity amongst the [[phylogenetics]] community for these reasons; a number of applications allow many demographic and evolutionary parameters to be estimated simultaneously.
| |
| | |
| As applied to [[statistical classification]], Bayesian inference has been used in recent years to develop algorithms for identifying [[e-mail spam]]. Applications which make use of Bayesian inference for spam filtering include [[CRM114 (program)|CRM114]], [[DSPAM]], [[Bogofilter]], [[SpamAssassin]], [[SpamBayes]], and [[Mozilla]]. Spam classification is treated in more detail in the article on the [[naive Bayes classifier]].
| |
| | |
| Solomonoff's [[Inductive inference]] is the theory of prediction based on observations; for example, predicting the next symbol based upon a given series of symbols. The only assumption is that the environment follows some unknown but computable probability distribution. It is a formal inductive framework that combines two well-studied principles of inductive inference: Bayesian statistics and [[Occam’s Razor]].<ref>Samuel Rathmanner and [[Marcus Hutter]]. "A Philosophical Treatise of Universal Induction". ''Entropy'', 13(6):1076–1136, 2011.</ref>
| |
| Solomonoff's universal prior probability of any prefix ''p'' of a computable sequence ''x'' is the sum of the probabilities of all programs (for a universal computer) that compute something starting with ''p''. Given some ''p'' and any computable but unknown probability distribution from which ''x'' is sampled, the universal prior and Bayes' theorem can be used to predict the yet unseen parts of ''x'' in optimal fashion.<ref>[http://arxiv.org/pdf/0709.1516 "The Problem of Old Evidence"], in §5 of "On Universal Prediction and Bayesian Confirmation", M. Hutter - Theoretical Computer Science, 2007 - Elsevier</ref><ref>[http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.186.8268&rep=rep1&type=pdf "Raymond J. Solomonoff"], Peter Gacs, Paul M. B. Vitanyi, 2011 cs.bu.edu</ref>
| |
| | |
| ===In the courtroom===
| |
| | |
| Bayesian inference can be used by jurors to coherently accumulate the evidence for and against a defendant, and to see whether, in totality, it meets their personal threshold for '[[beyond a reasonable doubt]]'.<ref>Dawid, A. P. and Mortera, J. (1996) "Coherent Analysis of Forensic Identification Evidence". ''[[Journal of the Royal Statistical Society]]'', Series B, 58, 425–443.</ref><ref>
| |
| Foreman, L. A.; Smith, A. F. M., and Evett, I. W. (1997). "Bayesian analysis of deoxyribonucleic acid profiling data in forensic identification applications (with discussion)". ''Journal of the Royal Statistical Society'', Series A, 160, 429–469.</ref><ref>Robertson, B. and Vignaux, G. A. (1995) ''Interpreting Evidence: Evaluating Forensic Science in the Courtroom''. John Wiley and Sons. Chichester. ISBN 978-0-471-96026-3</ref> Bayes' theorem is applied successively to all evidence presented, with the posterior from one stage becoming the prior for the next. The benefit of a Bayesian approach is that it gives the juror an unbiased, rational mechanism for combining evidence. It may be appropriate to explain Bayes' theorem to jurors in [[Bayes' rule|odds form]], as [[betting odds]] are more widely understood than probabilities. Alternatively, a [[Gambling and information theory|logarithmic approach]], replacing multiplication with addition, might be easier for a jury to handle.
| |
| | |
| [[Image:Ebits2c.png|thumb|256px|right|<center>Adding up evidence.</center>]]
| |
| | |
| If the existence of the crime is not in doubt, only the identity of the culprit, it has been suggested that the prior should be uniform over the qualifying population.<ref>Dawid, A. P. (2001) "Bayes' Theorem and Weighing Evidence by Juries"; http://128.40.111.250/evidence/content/dawid-paper.pdf</ref> For example, if 1,000 people could have committed the crime, the prior probability of guilt would be 1/1000.
| |
| | |
| The use of Bayes' theorem by jurors is controversial. In the United Kingdom, a defence [[expert witness]] explained Bayes' theorem to the jury in ''[[Regina versus Denis John Adams|R v Adams]]''. The jury convicted, but the case went to appeal on the basis that no means of accumulating evidence had been provided for jurors who did not wish to use Bayes' theorem. The Court of Appeal upheld the conviction, but it also gave the opinion that "To introduce Bayes' Theorem, or any similar method, into a criminal trial plunges the jury into inappropriate and unnecessary realms of theory and complexity, deflecting them from their proper task."
| |
| | |
| Gardner-Medwin<ref>Gardner-Medwin, A. (2005) "What Probability Should the Jury Address?". ''[[Significance (journal)|Significance]]'', 2 (1), March 2005</ref> argues that the criterion on which a verdict in a criminal trial should be based is ''not'' the probability of guilt, but rather the ''probability of the evidence, given that the defendant is innocent'' (akin to a [[frequentist]] [[p-value]]). He argues that if the posterior probability of guilt is to be computed by Bayes' theorem, the prior probability of guilt must be known. This will depend on the incidence of the crime, which is an unusual piece of evidence to consider in a criminal trial. Consider the following three propositions:
| |
| | |
| :'''A''' The known facts and testimony could have arisen if the defendant is guilty
| |
| :'''B''' The known facts and testimony could have arisen if the defendant is innocent
| |
| :'''C''' The defendant is guilty.
| |
| | |
| Gardner-Medwin argues that the jury should believe both A and not-B in order to convict. A and not-B implies the truth of C, but the reverse is not true. It is possible that B and C are both true, but in this case he argues that a jury should acquit, even though they know that they will be letting some guilty people go free. See also [[Lindley's paradox]].
| |
| | |
| ===Bayesian epistemology===
| |
| Bayesian epistemology is an [[epistemological]] movement that uses techniques of Bayesian inference as a means of justifying the rules of inductive logic.
| |
| | |
| [[Karl Popper]] and [[David Miller (philosopher)|David Miller]] have rejected the alleged rationality of Bayesianism, i.e. using Bayes rule to make epistemological inferences:<ref>David Miller: ''Critical Rationalism''</ref> It is prone to the same [[vicious circle]] as any other [[justificationism|justificationist]] epistemology, because it presupposes what it attempts to justify. According to this view, a rational interpretation of Bayesian inference would see it merely as a probabilistic version of [[falsifiability|falsification]], rejecting the belief, commonly held by Bayesians, that high likelihood achieved by a series of Bayesian updates would prove the hypothesis beyond any reasonable doubt, or even with likelihood greater than 0.
| |
| | |
| ===Other===
| |
| * The [[scientific method]] is sometimes interpreted as an application of Bayesian inference. In this view, Bayes' rule guides (or should guide) the updating of probabilities about [[hypothesis|hypotheses]] conditional on new observations or [[experiment]]s.<ref>Howson & Urbach (2005), Jaynes (2003)</ref>
| |
| * [[Bayesian search theory]] is used to search for lost objects.
| |
| * [[Bayesian inference in phylogeny]]
| |
| * [[Bayesian tool for methylation analysis]]
| |
| | |
| ==Bayes and Bayesian inference==
| |
| The problem considered by Bayes in Proposition 9 of his essay, "[[An Essay towards solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances]]", is the posterior distribution for the parameter ''a'' (the success rate) of the [[binomial distribution]].{{Citation needed|date=August 2010}}
| |
| | |
| What is "Bayesian" about Proposition 9 is that Bayes presented it as a ''probability'' for the parameter <math>a</math>. That is, not only can one compute probabilities for experimental outcomes, but also for the parameter which governs them, and the same [[algebra]] is used to make inferences of either kind. Interestingly, Bayes actually states his question in a way that might make the idea of assigning a probability distribution to a parameter palatable to a [[frequentist statistics|frequentist]]. He supposes that a [[billiard ball]] is thrown at random onto a billiard table, and that the probabilities ''p'' and ''q'' are the probabilities that subsequent billiard balls will fall above or below the first ball. By making the binomial parameter <math>a\,</math> depend on a random event, he cleverly escapes a philosophical quagmire that was an issue he most likely was not even aware of.
| |
| | |
| ==History==
| |
| {{Main|History of statistics#Bayesian statistics}}
| |
| | |
| The term ''Bayesian'' refers to [[Thomas Bayes]] (1702–1761), who proved a special case of what is now called [[Bayes' theorem]]. However, it was [[Pierre-Simon Laplace]] (1749–1827) who introduced a general version of the theorem and used it to approach problems in [[celestial mechanics]], medical statistics, [[Reliability (statistics)|reliability]], and [[jurisprudence]].<ref>{{cite book |first=Stephen M. |last=Stigler |year=1986 |title=The History of Statistics |publisher=Harvard University Press |chapter=Chapter 3 }}</ref> Early Bayesian inference, which used uniform priors following Laplace's [[principle of insufficient reason]], was called "[[inverse probability]]" (because it [[Inductive reasoning|infer]]s backwards from observations to parameters, or from effects to causes<ref name=Fienberg2006>{{cite journal |first=Stephen E. |last=Fienberg |year=2006 |url=http://ba.stat.cmu.edu/journal/2006/vol01/issue01/fienberg.pdf |title=When did Bayesian Inference Become ‘Bayesian’? |journal=Bayesian Analysis |volume=1 |issue=1 |pages=1–40 [p. 5] |doi= }}</ref>). After the 1920s, "inverse probability" was largely supplanted by a collection of methods that came to be called [[frequentist statistics]].<ref name=Fienberg2006/>
| |
| | |
| In the 20th century, the ideas of Laplace were further developed in two different directions, giving rise to ''objective'' and ''subjective'' currents in Bayesian practice. In the objective or "non-informative" current, the statistical analysis depends on only the model assumed, the data analyzed,<ref name=Bernardo>{{cite book |authorlink=José-Miguel Bernardo |first=José-Miguel |last=Bernardo |year=2005 |chapter=Reference analysis |title=Handbook of statistics |volume=25 |pages=17–90 |isbn= }}</ref> and the method assigning the prior, which differs from one objective Bayesian to another objective Bayesian. In the subjective or "informative" current, the specification of the prior depends on the belief (that is, propositions on which the analysis is prepared to act), which can summarize information from experts, previous studies, etc.
| |
| | |
| In the 1980s, there was a dramatic growth in research and applications of Bayesian methods, mostly attributed to the discovery of [[Markov chain Monte Carlo]] methods, which removed many of the computational problems, and an increasing interest in nonstandard, complex applications.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Wolpert |first=R. L. |year=2004 |title=A Conversation with James O. Berger |journal=Statistical Science |volume=19 |issue=1 |pages=205–218 |doi=10.1214/088342304000000053 |mr=2082155 }}</ref> Despite growth of Bayesian research, most undergraduate teaching is still based on frequentist statistics.<ref>{{cite paper |authorlink=José-Miguel Bernardo |first=José M. |last=Bernardo |year=2006 |url=http://www.ime.usp.br/~abe/ICOTS7/Proceedings/PDFs/InvitedPapers/3I2_BERN.pdf |title=A Bayesian mathematical statistics primer |work=ICOTS-7 }}</ref> Nonetheless, Bayesian methods are widely accepted and used, such as for example in the field of [[machine learning]].<ref name="ReferenceA">{{cite book |last=Bishop |first=C. M. |year=2007 |title=Pattern Recognition and Machine Learning |publisher=Springer |year=2007 |location=New York |isbn=0387310738 }}</ref>
| |
| | |
| ==See also==
| |
| * [[Bayes' theorem]]
| |
| * [[Bayesian Analysis (journal)|Bayesian Analysis]], the journal of the ISBA
| |
| * [[International Society for Bayesian Analysis]] (ISBA)
| |
| | |
| ==Notes==
| |
| {{Reflist|30em}}
| |
| | |
| ==References==
| |
| * Aster, Richard; Borchers, Brian, and Thurber, Clifford (2012). ''Parameter Estimation and Inverse Problems'', Second Edition, Elsevier. ISBN 0123850487, ISBN 978-0123850485
| |
| * {{Cite book|author=Bickel, Peter J. and Doksum, Kjell A.|title=Mathematical Statistics, Volume 1: Basic and Selected Topics|edition=Second (updated printing 2007)|year=2001|publisher=Pearson Prentice–Hall|isbn=0-13-850363-X}}
| |
| * [[George E. P. Box|Box, G. E. P.]] and Tiao, G. C. (1973) ''Bayesian Inference in Statistical Analysis'', Wiley, ISBN 0-471-57428-7
| |
| * {{cite book| author=Edwards, Ward| chapter=Conservatism in Human Information Processing|editor=Kleinmuntz, B.| title=Formal Representation of Human Judgment|publisher=Wiley|year=1968}}
| |
| * {{cite book| author=Edwards, Ward| chapter=Conservatism in Human Information Processing (excerpted)|editor=[[Daniel Kahneman]], [[Paul Slovic]] and [[Amos Tversky]]| title=Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=1982}}
| |
| * [[Edwin Thompson Jaynes|Jaynes E. T.]] (2003) ''Probability Theory: The Logic of Science'', CUP. ISBN 978-0-521-59271-0 ([http://www-biba.inrialpes.fr/Jaynes/prob.html Link to Fragmentary Edition of March 1996]).
| |
| * {{Cite book| title=Scientific Reasoning: the Bayesian Approach| author=[[Colin Howson|Howson, C.]] and Urbach, P.| publisher=[[Open Court Publishing Company]]| year=2005| edition=3rd | isbn=978-0-8126-9578-6}}
| |
| *{{Cite book| last1=Phillips|first1=L. D.|last2=Edwards|first2=Ward|chapter=Chapter 6: Conservatism in a Simple Probability Inference Task (''Journal of Experimental Psychology'' (1966) 72: 346-354) |title=A Science of Decision Making:The Legacy of Ward Edwards| editor=Jie W. Weiss and David J. Weiss| isbn=978-0-19-532298-9 |page=536 |date=October 2008 |publisher= Oxford University Press}}
| |
| | |
| ==Further reading==
| |
| | |
| ===Elementary===
| |
| The following books are listed in ascending order of probabilistic sophistication:
| |
| * Stone, JV (2013). Chapter 1 of book [http://jim-stone.staff.shef.ac.uk/BookBayes2012/BayesRuleBookMain.html "Bayes’ Rule: A Tutorial Introduction"], University of Sheffield.
| |
| * {{Cite book| title=Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach| author=[[Colin Howson]] and Peter Urbach| publisher=[[Open Court Publishing Company]]| year=2005| edition=3rd | isbn=978-0-8126-9578-6}}
| |
| * {{Cite book|author=Berry, Donald A.|title=Statistics: A Bayesian Perspective|publisher=Duxbury| year=1996|isbn=0-534-23476-3}}
| |
| *{{Cite book| author=[[Morris H. DeGroot]] and Mark J. Schervish |title=Probability and Statistics|edition=third|
| |
| isbn=978-0-201-52488-8|publisher=Addison-Wesley|year=2002}}
| |
| * Bolstad, William M. (2007) ''Introduction to Bayesian Statistics'': Second Edition, John Wiley ISBN 0-471-27020-2
| |
| *{{cite book |author=Winkler, Robert L |title=Introduction to Bayesian Inference and Decision |publisher=Probabilistic |year=2003 |isbn=0-9647938-4-9 |edition=2nd }} Updated classic textbook. Bayesian theory clearly presented.
| |
| * Lee, Peter M. ''Bayesian Statistics: An Introduction''. Fourth Edition (2012), John Wiley ISBN 978-1-1183-3257-3
| |
| * {{Cite book| title = Bayesian Methods for Data Analysis, Third Edition | publisher = Boca Raton, FL: Chapman and Hall/CRC | year = 2008 | isbn = 1-58488-697-8|author=Carlin, Bradley P. and Louis, Thomas A.}}
| |
| * {{Cite book| title = Bayesian Data Analysis, Second Edition | publisher = Boca Raton, FL: Chapman and Hall/CRC | year = 2003 | isbn = 1-58488-388-X|last1=Gelman|first1=Andrew|authorlink1=Andrew Gelman|last2=Carlin|first2=John B.|last3=Stern|first3=Hal S.|last4=Rubin|first4=Donald B.|authorlink4=Donald Rubin}}
| |
| | |
| ===Intermediate or advanced===
| |
| * {{Cite book|author=[[James Berger (statistician)|Berger, James O]]| title=Statistical Decision Theory and Bayesian Analysis| edition=Second|year=1985| publisher=Springer-Verlag|series=Springer Series in Statistics|isbn=0-387-96098-8}}
| |
| *{{Cite book|title=Bayesian Theory|publisher=Wiley|year=1994|authorlink1=José-Miguel Bernardo|last1=Bernardo|first=José M.|authorlink2=Adrian Smith (statistician)|last2=Smith|first2=Adrian F. M.|ref=harv|mr=|series=}}
| |
| * [[Morris H. DeGroot|DeGroot, Morris H.]], ''Optimal Statistical Decisions''. Wiley Classics Library. 2004. (Originally published (1970) by McGraw-Hill.) ISBN 0-471-68029-X.
| |
| * {{cite book|title=Theory of statistics|first=Mark J.|last=Schervish|publisher=Springer-Verlag|year=1995|isbn=0-387-94546-6}}
| |
| * Jaynes, E. T. (1998) [http://www-biba.inrialpes.fr/Jaynes/prob.html ''Probability Theory: The Logic of Science''].
| |
| * O'Hagan, A. and Forster, J. (2003) ''Kendall's Advanced Theory of Statistics'', Volume 2B: ''Bayesian Inference''. Arnold, New York. ISBN 0-340-52922-9.
| |
| * {{Cite book|author=Robert, Christian P|title=The Bayesian Choice – A Decision-Theoretic Motivation|publisher=Springer|year=2001|edition=second|isbn=0-387-94296-3}}
| |
| * [[Glenn Shafer]] and [[Judea Pearl|Pearl, Judea]], eds. (1988) ''Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems'', San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.
| |
| * Pierre Bessière et al. (2013), "[http://www.crcpress.com/product/isbn/9781439880326 Bayesian Programming]", CRC Press. ISBN 9781439880326
| |
| | |
| ==External links==
| |
| * {{springer|title=Bayesian approach to statistical problems|id=p/b015390}}
| |
| * [http://www.scholarpedia.org/article/Bayesian_statistics Bayesian Statistics] from Scholarpedia.
| |
| * [http://www.dcs.qmw.ac.uk/%7Enorman/BBNs/BBNs.htm Introduction to Bayesian probability] from Queen Mary University of London
| |
| * [http://webuser.bus.umich.edu/plenk/downloads.htm Mathematical Notes on Bayesian Statistics and Markov Chain Monte Carlo]
| |
| * [http://cocosci.berkeley.edu/tom/bayes.html Bayesian reading list], categorized and annotated by [http://psychology.berkeley.edu/faculty/profiles/tgriffiths.html Tom Griffiths]
| |
| * A. Hajek and S. Hartmann: [http://stephanhartmann.org/HajekHartmann_BayesEpist.pdf Bayesian Epistemology], in: J. Dancy et al. (eds.), A Companion to Epistemology. Oxford: Blackwell 2010, 93-106.
| |
| * S. Hartmann and J. Sprenger: [http://stephanhartmann.org/HartmannSprenger_BayesEpis.pdf Bayesian Epistemology], in: S. Bernecker and D. Pritchard (eds.), Routledge Companion to Epistemology. London: Routledge 2010, 609-620.
| |
| * [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-inductive/ ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'': "Inductive Logic"]
| |
| *[http://faculty-staff.ou.edu/H/James.A.Hawthorne-1/Hawthorne--Bayesian_Confirmation_Theory.pdf Bayesian Confirmation Theory]
| |
| * [http://www.faqs.org/faqs/ai-faq/neural-nets/part3/section-7.html What Is Bayesian Learning?]
| |
| | |
| {{Statistics|inference}}
| |
| | |
| {{DEFAULTSORT:Bayesian Inference}}
| |
| [[Category:Bayesian inference| ]]
| |
| [[Category:Statistical theory]]
| |
| [[Category:Statistical inference]]
| |
| [[Category:Logic and statistics]]
| |
| [[Category:Statistical forecasting]]
| |