Risk-neutral measure: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Enyokoyama
en>Yobot
m WP:CHECKWIKI error fixes using AWB (10500)
 
(One intermediate revision by one other user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
:''You might be looking for [[Computable function]], [[Computability theory]], [[Computation]], or [[Theory of computation]].''
I would like to introduce myself to you, I am Andrew and my spouse doesn't like it at all. To climb is something I truly enjoy performing. Office supervising is where her main income arrives from but she's already utilized for an additional one. I've usually cherished residing in Kentucky but now I'm contemplating other options.<br><br>Also visit my homepage :: clairvoyance ([http://torcidadonautico.com.br/profile/cokxd talks about it torcidadonautico.com.br])
'''Computability''' is the ability to solve a problem in an effective manner. It is a key topic of the field of [[computability theory]] within [[mathematical logic]] and the [[theory of computation]] within [[computer science]]. The computability of a problem is closely linked to the existence of an [[algorithm]] to solve the problem.
 
The most widely-studied models of computability are the [[Turing-computable function|Turing-computable]] and [[μ-recursive function]]s, and the [[lambda calculus]], all of which have computationally equivalent power. Other forms of computability are studied as well: computability notions weaker than Turing machines are studied in [[automata theory]], while computability notions stronger than Turing machines are studied in the field of [[hypercomputation]].
 
== Problems ==
 
A central idea in computability is that of a ('''computational''') '''[[computational problem|problem]]''', which is a task whose computability can be explored.
 
There are two key types of problems:
* A [[decision problem]] fixes a set ''S'', which may be a set of strings, natural numbers, or other objects taken from some larger set ''U''. A particular '''instance''' of the problem is to decide, given an element ''u'' of ''U'', whether ''u'' is in ''S''. For example, let ''U'' be the set of natural numbers and ''S'' the set of prime numbers. The corresponding decision problem corresponds to [[primality testing]].
* A [[function problem]] consists of a function ''f'' from a set ''U'' to a set ''V''. An instance of the problem is to compute, given an element ''u'' in ''U'', the corresponding element ''f''(''u'') in ''V''.  For example, ''U'' and ''V'' may be the set of all finite binary strings, and ''f'' may take a string and return the string obtained by reversing the digits of the input (so f(0101) = 1010).
Other types of problems include [[search problem]]s and [[optimization problem]]s.
 
One goal of computability theory is to determine which problems, or classes of problems, can be solved in each model of computation.
 
== Formal models of computation ==<!-- This section is linked from [[Abstract machine]] -->
{{main|Model of computation}}
A [[model of computation]] is a formal description of a particular type of computational process. The description often takes the form of an [[abstract machine]] that is meant to perform the task at hand. General models of computation equivalent to a [[Turing machine]] (See: [[Church–Turing thesis]]) include:
 
;[[Lambda calculus]]: A computation consists of an initial lambda expression (or two if you want to separate the function and its input) plus a finite sequence of lambda terms, each deduced from the preceding term by one application of [[Beta reduction]].
 
;[[Combinatory logic]]
:is a concept which has many similarities to <math>\lambda</math>-calculus, but also important differences exist (e.g. fixed point combinator '''Y''' has normal form in combinatory logic but not in <math>\lambda</math>-calculus). Combinatory logic was developed with great ambitions: understanding the nature of paradoxes, making foundations of mathematics more economic (conceptually), eliminating the notion of variables (thus clarifying their role in mathematics).
 
;[[μ-recursive function]]s: a computation consists of a μ-recursive function, ''i.e.'' its defining sequence, any input value(s) and a sequence of recursive functions appearing in the defining sequence with inputs and outputs.  Thus, if in the defining sequence of a recursive function <math>f(x)</math> the functions <math>g(x)</math> and <math>h(x,y)</math> appear, then terms of the form 'g(5)=7' or 'h(3,2)=10' might appear. Each entry in this sequence needs to be an application of a basic function or follow from the entries above by using [[Function composition (computer science)|composition]], [[primitive recursion]] or [[Mu-recursive function|μ-recursion]].  For instance if <math>f(x)=h(x,g(x))</math>, then for 'f(5)=3' to appear, terms like 'g(5)=6' and 'h(3,6)=3' must occur above.  The computation terminates only if the final term gives the value of the recursive function applied to the inputs.
 
;[[String rewriting system]]s: including [[Markov algorithm]], that uses [[grammar]]-like rules to operate on [[string (computer science)|strings]] of symbols; also [[Post canonical system]].
 
;[[Register machine]]
:is a theoretically interesting idealization of a computer. There are several variants. In most of them, each register can hold a natural number (of unlimited size), and the instructions are simple (and few in number), e.g. only decrementation (combined with conditional jump) and incrementation exist (and halting). The lack of the infinite (or dynamically growing) external store (seen at Turing machines) can be understood by replacing its role with [[Gödel numbering]] techniques: the fact that each register holds a natural number allows the possibility of representing a complicated thing (e.g. a sequence, or a matrix etc.) by an appropriate huge natural number — unambiguity of both representation and interpretation can be established by [[number theory|number theoretical]]  foundations of these techniques.
 
; [[Turing machine]]: Also similar to the finite state machine, except that the input is provided on an execution "tape", which the Turing machine can read from, write to, or move back and forth past its read/write "head". The tape is allowed to grow to arbitrary size. The Turing machine is capable of performing complex calculations which can have arbitrary duration. This model is perhaps the most important model of computation in computer science, as it simulates computation in the absence of predefined resource limits.
 
; [[Multi-tape Turing machine]]: Here, there may be more than one tape; moreover there may be multiple heads per tape.  Surprisingly, any computation that can be performed by this sort of machine can also be performed by an ordinary Turing machine, although the latter may be slower or require a larger total region of its tape.
 
;[[P′′]]
:Like Turing machines, P′′ uses an infinite tape of symbols (without random access), and a rather minimalistic set of instructions. But these instructions are very different, thus, unlike Turing machines, P′′ does not need to maintain a distinct state, because all “memory-like” functionality can be provided only by the tape. Instead of rewriting the current symbol, it can perform a [[modular arithmetic]] incrementation on it. P′′ has also a pair of instructions for a cycle, inspecting the blank symbol. Despite its minimalistic nature, it has become the parental formal language of an implemented and (for entertainment) used programming language called [[Brainfuck]].
 
In addition to the general computational models, some simpler computational models are useful for special, restricted applications.  [[Regular expressions]], for example,  specify string patterns in many contexts, from office productivity software to [[programming language]]s. Another formalism mathematically equivalent to regular expressions, [[finite state machines|Finite automata]] are used in circuit design and in some kinds of problem-solving. [[Context-free grammar]]s  specify programming language syntax.  Non-deterministic [[pushdown automaton|pushdown automata]] are another formalism equivalent to context-free grammars.
 
Different models of computation have the ability to do different tasks. One way to measure the power of a computational model is to study the class of [[formal language]]s that the model can generate; in such a way is the [[Chomsky hierarchy]] of languages is obtained.
 
Other restricted models of computation include:
 
; [[Deterministic finite automaton]](DFA): Also called a finite state machine.  All real computing devices in existence today can be modeled as a finite state machine, as all real computers operate on finite resources.  Such a machine has a set of states, and a set of state transitions which are affected by the input stream.  Certain states are defined to be accepting states.  An input stream is fed into the machine one character at a time, and the state transitions for the current state are compared to the input stream, and if there is a matching transition the machine may enter a new state.  If at the end of the input stream the machine is in an accepting state, then the whole input stream is accepted.
 
; [[Nondeterministic finite automaton]](NFA): it is another simple model of computation, although its processing sequence is not uniquely determined. It can be interpreted as taking multiple paths of computation simultaneously through a finite number of states. However, it is possible to prove that any NFA is reducible to an equivalent DFA.
 
; [[Pushdown automaton]]: Similar to the finite state machine, except that it has available an execution stack, which is allowed to grow to arbitrary size.  The state transitions additionally specify whether to add a symbol to the stack, or to remove a symbol from the stack. It is more powerful than a DFA due to its infinite-memory stack, although only the top element of the stack is accessible at any time.
 
== Power of automata ==
With these computational models in hand, we can determine what their limits are.  That is, what classes of [[Formal language|languages]] can they accept?
 
=== Power of finite state machines ===
 
{{cleanup|section|date=April 2009}}
 
Computer scientists call any language that can be accepted by a finite state machine a '''[[regular language]]'''.  Because of the restriction that the number of possible states in a finite state machine is finite, we can see that to find a language that is not regular, we must construct a language that would require an infinite number of states.
 
An example of such a language is the set of all strings consisting of the letters 'a' and 'b' which contain an equal number of the letter 'a' and 'b'.  To see why this language cannot be correctly recognized by a finite state machine, assume first that such a machine ''M'' exists.  ''M'' must have some number of states ''n''.  Now consider the string ''x'' consisting of <math>(n+1)</math> 'a's followed by <math>(n+1)</math> 'b's.
 
As ''M'' reads in ''x'', there must be some state in the machine that is repeated as it reads in the first series of 'a's, since there are <math>(n+1)</math> 'a's and only ''n'' states by the [[pigeonhole principle]].  Call this state ''S'', and further let ''d'' be the number of 'a's that our machine read in order to get from the first occurrence of ''S'' to some subsequent occurrence during the 'a' sequence.  We know, then, that at that second occurrence of ''S'', we can add in an additional ''d'' (where <math>d > 0</math>) 'a's and we will be again at state ''S''.  This means that we know that a string of <math>(n+d+1)</math> 'a's must end up in the same state as the string of <math>(n+1)</math> 'a's. This implies that if our machine accepts ''x'', it must also accept the string of <math>(n+d+1)</math> 'a's followed by <math>(n+1)</math> 'b's, which is not in the language of strings containing an equal number of 'a's and 'b's. In other words, ''M'' cannot correctly distinguish between a string of equal number of 'a's and 'b's and a string with <math>(n+d+1)</math> 'a's and <math>n+1</math> 'b's.
 
We know, therefore, that this language cannot be accepted correctly by any finite state machine, and is thus not a regular language.  A more general form of this result is called the [[Pumping lemma for regular languages]], which can be used to show that broad classes of languages cannot be recognized by a finite state machine.
 
=== Power of pushdown automata ===
Computer scientists define a language that can be accepted by a [[pushdown automaton]] as a '''[[Context-free language]]''', which can be specified as a '''[[Context-free grammar]]'''.  The language consisting of strings with equal numbers of 'a's and 'b's, which we showed was not a regular language, can be decided by a push-down automaton.  Also, in general, a push-down automaton can behave just like a finite-state machine, so it can decide any language which is regular.  This model of computation is thus strictly more powerful than finite state machines.
 
However, it turns out there are languages that cannot be decided by push-down automaton either.  The result is similar to that for regular expressions, and won't be detailed here.  There exists a [[Pumping lemma for context-free languages]].  An example of such a language is the set of prime numbers.
 
=== Power of Turing machines ===
[[Turing machine]]s can decide any context-free language, in addition to languages not decidable by a push-down automaton, such as the language consisting of prime numbers.  It is therefore a strictly more powerful model of computation.
 
Because Turing machines have the ability to "back up" in their input tape, it is possible for a Turing machine to run for a long time in a way that is not possible with the other computation models previously described.  It is possible to construct a Turing machine that will never finish running (halt) on some inputs.  We say that a Turing machine can decide a language if it eventually will halt on all inputs and give an answer.  A language that can be so decided is called a '''[[recursive language]]'''.  We can further describe Turing machines that will eventually halt and give an answer for any input in a language, but which may run forever for input strings which are not in the language.  Such Turing machines could tell us that a given string is in the language, but we may never be sure based on its behavior that a given string is not in a language, since it may run forever in such a case.  A language which is accepted by such a Turing machine is called a '''[[recursively enumerable language]]'''.
 
The Turing machine, it turns out, is an exceedingly powerful model of automata.  Attempts to amend the definition of a Turing machine to produce a more powerful machine have surprisingly met with failure.  For example, adding an extra tape to the Turing machine, giving it a 2-dimensional (or 3 or any-dimensional) infinite surface to work with can all be simulated by a Turing machine with the basic 1-dimensional tape.  These models are thus not more powerful.  In fact, a consequence of the [[Church-Turing thesis]] is that there is no reasonable model of computation which can decide languages that cannot be decided by a Turing machine.
 
The question to ask then is: do there exist languages which are recursively enumerable, but not recursive?  And, furthermore, are there languages which are not even recursively enumerable?
 
==== The halting problem ====
{{Main|Halting problem}}
 
The halting problem is one of the most famous problems in computer science, because it has profound implications on the theory of computability and on how we use computers in everyday practice.  The problem can be phrased:
 
: ''Given a description of a Turing machine and its initial input, determine whether the program, when executed on this input, ever halts (completes). The alternative is that it runs forever without halting.''
 
Here we are asking not a simple question about a prime number or a palindrome, but we are instead turning the tables and asking a Turing machine to answer a question about another Turing machine.  It can be shown (See main article: [[Halting problem]]) that it is not possible to construct a Turing machine that can answer this question in all cases.
 
That is, the only general way to know for sure if a given program will halt on a particular input in all cases is simply to run it and see if it halts.  If it does halt, then you know it halts.  If it doesn't halt, however, you may never know if it will eventually halt.  The language consisting of all Turing machine descriptions paired with all possible input streams on which those Turing machines will eventually halt, is not recursive. The halting problem is therefore called non-computable or '''[[undecidable problem|undecidable]]'''.
 
An extension of the halting problem is called [[Rice's Theorem]], which states that it is undecidable (in general) whether a given language possesses any specific nontrivial property.
 
==== Beyond recursively enumerable languages ====
The halting problem is easy to solve, however, if we allow that the Turing machine that decides it may run forever when given input which is a representation of a Turing machine that does not itself halt.  The halting language is therefore recursively enumerable.  It is possible to construct languages which are not even recursively enumerable, however.
 
A simple example of such a language is the complement of the halting language; that is the language consisting of all Turing machines paired with input strings where the Turing machines do ''not'' halt on their input.  To see that this language is not recursively enumerable, imagine that we construct a Turing machine ''M'' which is able to give a definite answer for all such Turing machines, but that it may run forever on any Turing machine that does eventually halt.  We can then construct another Turing machine <math>M'</math> that simulates the operation of this machine, along with simulating directly the execution of the machine given in the input as well, by interleaving the execution of the two programs.  Since the direct simulation will eventually halt if the program it is simulating halts, and since by assumption the simulation of ''M'' will eventually halt if the input program would never halt, we know that <math>M'</math> will eventually have one of its parallel versions halt.  <math>M'</math> is thus a decider for the halting problem.  We have previously shown, however, that the halting problem is undecidable.  We have a contradiction, and we have thus shown that our assumption that ''M'' exists is incorrect.  The complement of the halting language is therefore not recursively enumerable.
 
== Concurrency-based models ==
A number of computational models based on [[Concurrency (computer science)|concurrency]] have been developed, including the [[Parallel Random Access Machine]] and the [[Petri net]].  These models of concurrent computation still do not implement any mathematical functions that cannot be implemented by Turing machines.
 
== Stronger models of computation ==
The [[Church-Turing thesis]] conjectures that there is no effective model of computing that can compute more mathematical functions than a Turing machine. Computer scientists have imagined many varieties of '''[[hypercomputer]]s''', models of computation that go beyond Turing computability.
 
=== Infinite execution ===
{{Main|Zeno machine}}
Imagine a machine where each step of the computation requires half the time of the previous step.  If we normalize to 1 time unit the amount of time required for the first step, the execution would require
 
:<math>1 + {1 \over 2} + {1 \over 4} + \cdots</math>
 
time to run.  This infinite series converges to 2 time units, which means that this Turing machine can run an infinite execution in 2 time units.  This machine is capable of deciding the halting problem by directly simulating the execution of the machine in question. By extension, any convergent series would work. Assuming that the series converges to a value ''n'', the Turing machine would complete an infinite execution in ''n'' time units.
 
=== Oracle machines ===
{{Main|Oracle machine}}
So-called Oracle machines have access to various "oracles" which provide the solution to specific undecidable problems.  For example, the Turing machine may have a "halting oracle" which answers immediately whether a given Turing machine will ever halt on a given input.  These machines are a central topic of study in [[recursion theory]].
 
=== Limits of hyper-computation ===
Even these machines, which seemingly represent the limit of automata that we could imagine, run into their own limitations.  While each of them can solve the halting problem for a Turing machine, they cannot solve their own version of the halting problem.  For example, an Oracle machine cannot answer the question of whether a given Oracle machine will ever halt.
 
==See also==
*[[Automata theory]]
*[[Abstract machine]]
*[[List of undecidable problems]]
*[[Computational complexity theory]]
*[[Computability logic]]
*[[List of important publications in theoretical computer science#Computability|Important publications in computability]]
 
== References ==
 
* {{cite book|author = [[Michael Sipser]] | year = 1997 | title = Introduction to the Theory of Computation | publisher = PWS Publishing | isbn = 0-534-94728-X}} Part Two: Computability Theory, Chapters 3–6, pp.&nbsp;123–222.
* {{cite book|author = [[Christos Papadimitriou]] | year = 1993 | title = Computational Complexity | publisher = Addison Wesley | edition = 1st | isbn = 0-201-53082-1}} Chapter 3: Computability, pp.&nbsp;57–70.
* {{cite book|author = [[S. Barry Cooper]] | year = 2004 | title = Computability Theory | publisher = Chapman & Hall/CRC | edition = 1st | isbn = 978-1-58488-237-4}}
 
{{computable knowledge}}
 
[[Category:Computability theory| ]]
[[Category:Theory of computation| ]]

Latest revision as of 09:21, 23 November 2014

I would like to introduce myself to you, I am Andrew and my spouse doesn't like it at all. To climb is something I truly enjoy performing. Office supervising is where her main income arrives from but she's already utilized for an additional one. I've usually cherished residing in Kentucky but now I'm contemplating other options.

Also visit my homepage :: clairvoyance (talks about it torcidadonautico.com.br)