|
|
Line 1: |
Line 1: |
| {{Probability fundamentals}}
| | Hello! My name is Jodie. <br>It is a little about myself: I live in Italy, my city of Malalbergo. <br>It's called often Northern or cultural capital of BO. I've married 2 years ago.<br>I have two children - a son (Verona) and the daughter (Raymundo). We all like Equestrianism.<br>[http://www.eurosummit13.com/content/forevertranscriptioncomlegal-transcription-servicesphp-blank-techniques legal transcription courses] |
| In Kolmogorov's [[probability theory]], the [[probability]] ''P'' of some [[event (probability theory)|event]] ''E'', denoted <math>P(E)</math>, is usually defined in such a way that ''P'' satisfies the '''Kolmogorov axioms''', named after the famous [[Russia|Russian]] [[mathematician]] [[Andrey Kolmogorov]], which are described below.
| |
| | |
| These assumptions can be summarised as: Let (Ω, ''F'', ''P'') be a [[measure space]] with ''P''(Ω)=1. Then (Ω, ''F'', ''P'') is a [[probability space]], with sample space Ω, event space ''F'' and probability measure ''P''.
| |
| | |
| An alternative approach to formalising probability, favoured by some [[Bayesian theory|Bayesians]], is given by [[Cox's theorem]].
| |
| | |
| == Axioms ==
| |
| | |
| === First axiom ===
| |
| The probability of an event is a non-negative real number:
| |
| :<math>P(E)\in\mathbb{R}, P(E)\geq 0 \qquad \forall E\in F</math>
| |
| | |
| where <math>F</math> is the event space. In particular, <math>P(E)</math> is always finite, in contrast with more general [[measure theory]]. Theories which assign [[negative probability]] relax the first axiom.
| |
| | |
| === Second axiom ===
| |
| {{seealso|Unitarity (physics)}}
| |
| This is the assumption of [[unit measure]]: that the probability that some [[elementary event]] in the entire sample space will occur is 1. More specifically, there are no elementary events outside the sample space.
| |
| : <math>P(\Omega) = 1.</math>
| |
| | |
| This is often overlooked in some mistaken probability calculations; if you cannot precisely define the whole sample space, then the probability of any subset cannot be defined either.
| |
| | |
| ===Third axiom===
| |
| This is the assumption of [[σ-additivity]]:
| |
| : Any [[countable]] sequence of [[disjoint sets|disjoint]] (synonymous with ''mutually exclusive'') events <math>E_1, E_2, ...</math> satisfies
| |
| ::<math>P(E_1 \cup E_2 \cup \cdots) = \sum_{i=1}^\infty P(E_i).</math>
| |
| Some authors consider merely [[finitely additive]] probability spaces, in which case one just needs an [[algebra of sets]], rather than a [[σ-algebra]]. [[Quasiprobability distribution]]s in general relax the third axiom.
| |
| | |
| ==Consequences==
| |
| From the [[Kolmogorov]] axioms, one can deduce other useful rules for calculating probabilities.
| |
| | |
| ===Monotonicity===
| |
| | |
| : <math>\quad\text{if}\quad A\subseteq B\quad\text{then}\quad P(A)\leq P(B).</math>
| |
| | |
| ===The probability of the empty set===
| |
| | |
| : <math>P(\emptyset)=0.</math>
| |
| | |
| ===The numeric bound===
| |
| It immediately follows from the monotonicity property that
| |
| : <math>0\leq P(E)\leq 1\qquad \text{∀} E\in F.</math>
| |
| | |
| ==Proofs==
| |
| The proofs of these properties are both interesting and insightful. They illustrate the power of the third axiom,
| |
| and its interaction with the remaining two axioms. When studying [[axiomatic]] [[probability theory]], many deep consequences follow from merely these three axioms.
| |
| In order to verify the monotonicity property, we set <math>E_1=A</math> and <math>E_2=B\backslash A</math>,
| |
| where <math>\quad A\subseteq B \text{ and } E_i=\emptyset</math> for <math>i\geq 3</math>. It is easy to see that the sets <math>E_i</math>
| |
| are pairwise disjoint and <math>E_1\cup E_2\cup\ldots=B</math>. Hence,
| |
| we obtain from the third axiom that
| |
| : <math>P(A)+P(B\backslash A)+\sum_{i=3}^\infty P(\emptyset)=P(B).</math>
| |
| Since the left-hand side of this equation is a series of non-negative numbers, and that it converges to
| |
| <math>P(B)</math> which is finite, we obtain both <math>P(A)\leq P(B)</math> and <math>P(\emptyset)=0</math>.
| |
| The second part of the statement is seen by contradiction: if <math>P(\emptyset)=a</math> then the left hand side is not less than
| |
| : <math>\sum_{i=3}^\infty P(E_i)=\sum_{i=3}^\infty P(\emptyset)=\sum_{i=3}^\infty a = \begin{cases} 0 & \text{if } a=0, \\ \infty & \text{if } a>0. \end{cases}</math>
| |
| If <math>a>0</math> then we obtain a contradiction, because the sum does not exceed <math>P(B)</math> which is finite. Thus, <math>a=0</math>. We have shown as a byproduct of the proof of monotonicity that <math>P(\emptyset)=0</math>.
| |
| | |
| ==More consequences==
| |
| Another important property is:
| |
| | |
| : <math>P(A \cup B) = P(A) + P(B) - P(A \cap B).</math>
| |
| | |
| This is called the addition law of probability, or the sum rule.
| |
| That is, the probability that ''A'' ''or'' ''B'' will happen is the sum of the
| |
| probabilities that ''A'' will happen and that ''B'' will happen, minus the
| |
| probability that both ''A'' ''and'' ''B'' will happen. This can be extended to the [[inclusion-exclusion principle]].
| |
| | |
| : <math>P(\Omega\setminus E) = 1 - P(E)</math>
| |
| | |
| That is, the probability that any event will ''not'' happen is 1 minus the probability that it will.
| |
| | |
| ==Simple example: coin toss==
| |
| Consider a single coin-toss, and assume that the coin will either land heads (H) or tails (T) (but not both). No assumption is made as to whether the coin is fair.
| |
| | |
| We may define: | |
| | |
| : <math>\Omega = \{H,T\}</math>
| |
| : <math>F = \{\emptyset, \{H\}, \{T\}, \{H,T\}\}</math>
| |
| | |
| Kolmogorov's axioms imply that:
| |
| | |
| : <math>P(\emptyset) = 0</math>
| |
| The probability of ''neither'' heads ''nor'' tails, is 0.
| |
| | |
| : <math>P(\{H,T\}) = 1</math>
| |
| The probability of ''either'' heads ''or'' tails, is 1.
| |
| | |
| : <math>P(\{H\}) + P(\{T\}) = 1</math>
| |
| The sum of the probability of heads and the probability of tails, is 1.
| |
| | |
| == See also ==
| |
| * [[Law of total probability]]
| |
| * [[Measure (mathematics)]]
| |
| * [[Borel Algebra]]
| |
| * [[Sigma-algebra | σ-Algebra]]
| |
| * [[Probability theory]]
| |
| * [[Set theory]]
| |
| * [[Conditional probability]]
| |
| * [[Quasiprobability]]
| |
| | |
| {{No footnotes|date=November 2010}}
| |
| | |
| ==Further reading==
| |
| * Von Plato, Jan, 2005, "Grundbegriffe der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung" in [[Ivor Grattan-Guinness|Grattan-Guinness, I.]], ed., ''Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics''. Elsevier: 960-69. (in English)
| |
| * {{citation|author1=Glenn Shafer|author2=Vladimir Vovk|title=The origins and legacy of Kolmogorov’s Grundbegriffe|url=http://www.probabilityandfinance.com/articles/04.pdf}}
| |
| | |
| ==External links==
| |
| * [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/probability-interpret/#KolProCal Kolmogorov`s probability calculus], Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
| |
| * [http://mws.cs.ru.nl/mwiki/prob_1.html#M2 Formal definition] of probability in the [[Mizar system]], and the [http://mmlquery.mizar.org/cgi-bin/mmlquery/emacs_search?input=(symbol+Probability+%7C+notation+%7C+constructor+%7C+occur+%7C+th)+ordered+by+number+of+ref list of theorems] formally proved about it.
| |
| | |
| {{DEFAULTSORT:Probability Axioms}}
| |
| [[Category:Probability theory]]
| |
| [[Category:Mathematical axioms]]
| |
Hello! My name is Jodie.
It is a little about myself: I live in Italy, my city of Malalbergo.
It's called often Northern or cultural capital of BO. I've married 2 years ago.
I have two children - a son (Verona) and the daughter (Raymundo). We all like Equestrianism.
legal transcription courses