|
|
(One intermediate revision by one other user not shown) |
Line 1: |
Line 1: |
| {{See also|Table of logic symbols}}
| | The author's title is Zachery Dismukes and he considers it sounds quite good. Providing databases is his profession. Georgia happens to be his living area. Itis not a frequent thing but what I prefer doing does ceramics but I haven't created a dime<br><br>Feel free to surf to my web page :: [http://www.shadygamer.com/members/lkerry.169297/ http://prolexins.net/] |
| In [[logic]], '''proof by contradiction''' is a form of [[Mathematical proof|proof]] that establishes the [[Truth#Formal theories|truth]] or [[validity]] of a [[proposition]] by showing that the proposition's being false would imply a [[contradiction]]. Proof by contradiction is also known as '''indirect proof''', '''apagogical argument''', '''proof by assuming the opposite''', and '''''reductio ad impossibilem'''''. It is a particular kind of the more general form of argument known as ''[[reductio ad absurdum]]''.
| |
| | |
| [[G. H. Hardy]] described proof by contradiction as "one of a mathematician's finest weapons", saying "It is a far finer gambit than any [[chess]] [[gambit]]: a chess player may offer the sacrifice of a pawn or even a piece, but a mathematician offers the game."<ref>[[G. H. Hardy]], ''[[A Mathematician's Apology]]; Cambridge University Press, 1992. ISBN 9780521427067. ''[http://books.google.com/books?id=beImvXUGD-MC&pg=PA94 p. 94].</ref>
| |
| | |
| == Examples ==
| |
| | |
| ===Irrationality of the square root of 2===
| |
| | |
| A classic proof by contradiction from mathematics is the [[Square root of 2#Proof by infinite descent|proof that the square root of 2 is irrational]].<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.math.utah.edu/~pa/math/q1.html|title=Why is the square root of 2 irrational?|last=Alfield|first=Peter|date=16 August 1996|work=Understanding Mathematics, a study guide|publisher=Department of Mathematics, University of Utah|accessdate=6 February 2013}}</ref> If it were [[rational number|rational]], it could be expressed as a fraction ''a''/''b'' in [[lowest terms]], where ''a'' and ''b'' are [[integers]], at least one of which is [[odd number|odd]]. But if ''a''/''b'' = √{{overline|2}}, then ''a''<sup>2</sup> = 2''b''<sup>2</sup>. Therefore ''a''<sup>2</sup> must be even.
| |
| Because the square of an odd number is odd, that in turn implies that ''a'' is even. This means that ''b'' must be odd because a/b is in lowest terms.
| |
| | |
| On the other hand, if ''a'' is even, then ''a''<sup>2</sup> is a multiple of 4. If ''a''<sup>2</sup> is a multiple of 4 and ''a''<sup>2</sup> = 2''b''<sup>2</sup>, then 2''b''<sup>2</sup> is a multiple of 4, and therefore ''b''<sup>2</sup> is even, and so is ''b''.
| |
| | |
| So ''b'' is odd and even, a contradiction. Therefore the initial assumption—that √{{overline|2}} can be expressed as a fraction—must be false.
| |
| | |
| ===The length of the hypotenuse ===
| |
| The method of proof by contradiction has also been used to show that for any [[Degeneracy (mathematics)|non-degenerate]] [[right triangle]], the length of the hypotenuse is less than the sum of the lengths of the two remaining sides.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.cs.utexas.edu/~pstone/Courses/313Hfall12/resources/week2a-pp4.pdf|title=Logic, Sets, and Functions: Honors|last=Stone|first=Peter|work=Course materials|publisher=Department of Computer Sciences, The University of Texas at Austin|accessdate=6 February 2013|location=pp 14–23}}</ref> The proof relies on the [[Pythagorean theorem]]. Letting ''c'' be the length of the hypotenuse and ''a'' and ''b'' the lengths of the legs, the claim is that ''a'' + ''b'' > ''c''.
| |
| | |
| The claim is negated to assume that ''a'' + ''b'' ≤ ''c''. Squaring both sides results in (''a'' + ''b'')<sup>2</sup> ≤ ''c''<sup>2</sup> or, equivalently, ''a''<sup>2</sup> + 2''ab'' + ''b''<sup>2</sup> ≤ ''c''<sup>2</sup>. A triangle is non-degenerate if each edge has positive length, so it may be assumed that ''a'' and ''b'' are greater than 0. Therefore, ''a''<sup>2</sup> + ''b''<sup>2</sup> < ''a''<sup>2</sup> + 2''ab'' + ''b''<sup>2</sup> ≤ ''c''<sup>2</sup>. The [[transitive relation]] may be reduced to ''a''<sup>2</sup> + ''b''<sup>2</sup> < ''c''<sup>2</sup>. It is known from the Pythagorean theorem that ''a''<sup>2</sup> + ''b''<sup>2</sup> = ''c''<sup>2</sup>. This results in a contradiction since strict inequality and equality are [[Mutually exclusive events|mutually exclusive]]. The latter was a result of the Pythagorean theorem and the former the assumption that ''a'' + ''b'' ≤ ''c''. The contradiction means that it is impossible for both to be true and it is known that the Pythagorean theorem holds. It follows that the assumption that ''a'' + ''b'' ≤ ''c'' must be false and hence ''a'' + ''b'' > ''c'', proving the claim.
| |
| | |
| ===No least positive rational number===
| |
| | |
| <!---redundant, compared with the lead---distinction between proving p and ¬p doesn't matter in classical logic; rule for proving p isn't accepted in intuitionistic logic---
| |
| Say we wish to disprove proposition ''p''. The procedure is to show that assuming ''p'' leads to a logical contradiction. Thus, according to the law of non-contradiction, ''p'' must be false.
| |
| | |
| Say instead we wish to prove proposition ''p''. We can proceed by assuming "not ''p''" (i.e. that ''p'' is false), and show that it leads to a logical contradiction. Thus, according to the law of non-contradiction, "not ''p''" must be false, and so, according to the [[law of the excluded middle]], ''p'' is true.
| |
| | |
| In symbols:
| |
|
| |
| To disprove ''p'': one uses the [[tautology (logic)|tautology]] (''p'' → (''R'' ∧ ¬''R'')) → ¬''p'', where ''R'' is any proposition and the ∧ symbol is taken to mean "and". Assuming ''p'', one proves ''R'' and ''¬R'', and concludes from this that ''p'' → (''R'' ∧ ¬''R''). This and the tautology together imply ''¬p''.
| |
| | |
| To prove ''p'': one uses the tautology (¬''p'' → (''R'' ∧ ¬''R'')) → ''p'' where ''R'' is any proposition. Assuming ¬''p'', one proves ''R'' and ¬''R'', and concludes from this that ¬''p'' → (''R'' ∧ ¬''R''). This and the tautology together imply ''p''.
| |
| | |
| For a simple example of the first kind,
| |
| --->
| |
| Consider the proposition, ''P'': "there is no smallest rational number greater than 0". In a proof by contradiction, we start by assuming the opposite, ¬''P'': that there ''is'' a smallest rational number, say, ''r''.
| |
| | |
| Now ''r''/2 is a rational number greater than 0 and smaller than ''r''.
| |
| (In the above symbolic argument, "''r''/2 is the smallest rational number" would be ''Q'' and "''r'' (which is different from ''r''/2) is the smallest rational number" would be ¬''Q''.)
| |
| But that contradicts our initial assumption, ¬''P'', that ''r'' was the ''smallest'' rational number. So we can conclude that the original proposition, ''P'', must be true — "there is no smallest rational number greater than 0".
| |
| <!---redundant---
| |
| [Note: the choice of which statement is ''R'' and which is ¬''R'' is arbitrary.]
| |
| --->
| |
| <!---doubtful distinction between proving p and ¬p---
| |
| It is common to use this first type of argument with propositions such as the one above, concerning the ''non''-existence of some mathematical object. One assumes that such an object exists, and then proves that this would lead to a contradiction; thus, such an object does not exist.
| |
| --->
| |
| ===Other===
| |
| For other examples, see [[Square root of 2#Proofs of irrationality|proof that the square root of 2 is not rational]] (where indirect proofs different from the [[#Irrationality of the square root of 2|above]] one can be found) and [[Cantor's diagonal argument]].
| |
| <!---last paragraph moved down--->
| |
| | |
| ==In mathematical logic==<!---this doesn't belong to the example section--->
| |
| In [[mathematical logic]], the proof by contradiction is represented as:
| |
| | |
| : If
| |
| ::<math>S \cup \{ P \} \vdash \mathbb{F}</math>
| |
| : then
| |
| ::<math>S \vdash \neg P.</math>
| |
| | |
| or
| |
| | |
| : If
| |
| ::<math>S \cup \{ \neg P \} \vdash \mathbb{F}</math>
| |
| : then
| |
| ::<math>S \vdash P.</math>
| |
| | |
| In the above, ''P'' is the proposition we wish to disprove respectively prove; and ''S'' is a set of statements, which are the [[premise]]s—these could be, for example, the [[axiom]]s of the theory we are working in, or earlier [[theorem]]s we can build upon. We consider ''P'', or the negation of ''P'', in addition to ''S''; if this leads to a logical contradiction ''F'', then we can conclude that the statements in ''S'' lead to the negation of ''P'', or ''P'' itself, respectively.
| |
| | |
| Note that the [[union (set theory)|set-theoretic union]], in some contexts closely related to [[logical disjunction]] (or), is used here for sets of statements in such a way that it is more related to [[logical conjunction]] (and).
| |
| | |
| <!---last paragraph of former section "In mathematics" moved to here:--->
| |
| <!---doubtful distinction between proving p and ¬p---
| |
| On the other hand, it is also common to use arguments of the second type concerning the ''existence'' of some mathematical object.
| |
| --->
| |
| A particular kind of indirect proof assumes that some object doesn't exist, and then proves that this would lead to a contradiction; thus, such an object must exist. Although it is quite freely used in mathematical proofs, not every [[philosophy of mathematics|school of mathematical thought]] accepts this kind of argument as universally valid. See further [[Nonconstructive proof]].
| |
| | |
| ==Notation==
| |
| <!-- This section is linked from [[Hand of Eris]]. -->
| |
| Proofs by contradiction sometimes end with the word "Contradiction!". [[Isaac Barrow]] and Baermann used the notation Q.E.A., for "''quod est absurdum''" ("which is absurd"), along the lines of [[Q.E.D.]], but this notation is rarely used today.<ref>[http://robin.hartshorne.net/QED.html Hartshorne on QED and related]</ref> A graphical symbol sometimes used for contradictions is a downwards zigzag arrow "lightning" symbol (U+21AF: ↯), for example in Davey and Priestley.<ref>B. Davey and H.A. Priestley, Introduction to lattices and order, Cambridge University Press, 2002.</ref> Others sometimes used include a pair of [[Hand of Eris|opposing arrows]] (as <math>\rightarrow\!\leftarrow</math> or <math>\Rightarrow\!\Leftarrow</math>), struck-out arrows (<math>\nleftrightarrow</math>), a stylized form of hash (such as U+2A33: ⨳), or the "reference mark" (U+203B: ※).<ref>The Comprehensive LaTeX Symbol List, pg. 20. http://www.ctan.org/tex-archive/info/symbols/comprehensive/symbols-a4.pdf</ref><ref>Gary Hardegree, ''Introduction to Modal Logic'', Chapter 2, pg. II–2. http://people.umass.edu/gmhwww/511/pdf/c02.pdf</ref> The "up tack" symbol (U+22A5: ⊥) used by philosophers and logicians (see contradiction) also appears, but is often avoided due to its usage for [[orthogonality]].
| |
| | |
| ==See also==
| |
| *[[Proof by contrapositive]]
| |
| | |
| ==References==
| |
| {{Reflist}}
| |
| | |
| ==Further reading==
| |
| {{wikibooks|1=Mathematical Proof|2=Methods of Proof/Proof by Contradiction|3=Proof by Contradiction}}
| |
| *{{cite book|last=Franklin|first=James|title=Proof in Mathematics: An Introduction|year=2011|publisher=Kew|location=chapter 6|isbn=978-0-646-54509-7|url=http://www.maths.unsw.edu.au/~jim/proofs.html}}
| |
| | |
| ==External links==
| |
| *[http://zimmer.csufresno.edu/~larryc/proofs/proofs.contradict.html Proof by Contradiction] from Larry W. Cusick's [http://zimmer.csufresno.edu/~larryc/proofs/proofs.html How To Write Proofs]
| |
| | |
| {{DEFAULTSORT:Proof By Contradiction}}
| |
| [[Category:Mathematical proofs]]
| |
| [[Category:Methods of proof]]
| |
| [[Category:Theorems in propositional logic]]
| |
The author's title is Zachery Dismukes and he considers it sounds quite good. Providing databases is his profession. Georgia happens to be his living area. Itis not a frequent thing but what I prefer doing does ceramics but I haven't created a dime
Feel free to surf to my web page :: http://prolexins.net/