Polynomial ring: Difference between revisions
en>Linas |
en>Imaginatorium m →Definition: move ref by one word |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
In [[set theory]], the concept of [[cardinality]] is significantly developable without recourse to actually defining [[cardinal numbers]] as objects in theory itself (this is in fact a viewpoint taken by [[Gottlob Frege|Frege]]; [[Frege cardinal]]s are basically [[equivalence class]]es on the entire [[universe (mathematics)|universe]] of sets which are [[equinumerous]]). The concepts are developed by defining [[equinumerous|equinumerosity]] in terms of functions and the concepts of [[injective function|one-to-one]] and [[surjective function|onto]] (injectivity and surjectivity); this gives us a pseudo-ordering relation | |||
:<math>A \leq_c B\quad \iff\quad (\exists f)(f : A \to B\ \mathrm{is\ injective})</math> | |||
on the whole universe by size. It is not a true ordering because the [[trichotomy (mathematics)|trichotomy law]] need not hold: if both <math>A \leq_c B</math> and <math>B \leq_c A</math>, it is true by the [[Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem]] that <math>A =_c B</math> i.e. ''A'' and ''B'' are equinumerous, but they do not have to be literally equal; that at least one case holds turns out to be equivalent to the [[Axiom of choice]]. | |||
Nevertheless, most of the ''interesting'' results on cardinality and its arithmetic can be expressed merely with =<sub>c</sub>. | |||
The goal of a '''cardinal assignment''' is to assign to every set ''A'' a specific, unique set which is only dependent on the cardinality of ''A''. This is in accordance with [[Georg Cantor|Cantor]]'s original vision of a cardinals: to take a set and abstract its elements into canonical "units" and collect these units into another set, such that the only thing special about this set is its size. These would be totally ordered by the relation <math>\leq_c</math> and =<sub>c</sub> would be true equality. As Y. N. Moschovakis says, however, this is mostly an exercise in mathematical elegance, and you don't gain much unless you are "allergic to subscripts." However, there are various valuable applications of "real" cardinal numbers in various [[model theory|models]] of set theory. | |||
In modern set theory, we usually use the [[Von Neumann cardinal assignment]] which uses the theory of ordinal numbers and the full power of the axioms of [[Axiom of choice|choice]] and [[Axiom of replacement|replacement]]. Cardinal assignments do need the full axiom of choice, if we want a decent cardinal arithmetic and an assignment for ''all'' sets. | |||
== Cardinal assignment without the axiom of choice == | |||
Formally, assuming the axiom of choice, cardinality of a set ''X'' is the least ordinal α such that there is a bijection between ''X'' and α. This definition is known as the [[von Neumann cardinal assignment]]. If the axiom of choice is not assumed we need to do something different. The oldest definition of the cardinality of a set ''X'' (implicit in Cantor and explicit in Frege and [[Principia Mathematica]]) is as the set of all sets which are equinumerous with ''X'': this does not work in [[ZFC]] or other related systems of [[axiomatic set theory]] because this collection is too large to be a set, but it does work in [[type theory]] and in [[New Foundations]] and related systems. However, if we restrict from this class to those equinumerous with ''X'' that have the least [[rank (set theory)|rank]], then it will work (this is a trick due to [[Dana Scott]]: it works because the collection of objects with any given rank is a set). | |||
==References== | |||
*Moschovakis, Yiannis N. ''Notes on Set Theory''. New York: Springer-Verlag, 1994. | |||
[[Category:Set theory]] | |||
[[Category:Cardinal numbers]] |
Revision as of 09:16, 30 January 2014
In set theory, the concept of cardinality is significantly developable without recourse to actually defining cardinal numbers as objects in theory itself (this is in fact a viewpoint taken by Frege; Frege cardinals are basically equivalence classes on the entire universe of sets which are equinumerous). The concepts are developed by defining equinumerosity in terms of functions and the concepts of one-to-one and onto (injectivity and surjectivity); this gives us a pseudo-ordering relation
on the whole universe by size. It is not a true ordering because the trichotomy law need not hold: if both and , it is true by the Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem that i.e. A and B are equinumerous, but they do not have to be literally equal; that at least one case holds turns out to be equivalent to the Axiom of choice.
Nevertheless, most of the interesting results on cardinality and its arithmetic can be expressed merely with =c.
The goal of a cardinal assignment is to assign to every set A a specific, unique set which is only dependent on the cardinality of A. This is in accordance with Cantor's original vision of a cardinals: to take a set and abstract its elements into canonical "units" and collect these units into another set, such that the only thing special about this set is its size. These would be totally ordered by the relation and =c would be true equality. As Y. N. Moschovakis says, however, this is mostly an exercise in mathematical elegance, and you don't gain much unless you are "allergic to subscripts." However, there are various valuable applications of "real" cardinal numbers in various models of set theory.
In modern set theory, we usually use the Von Neumann cardinal assignment which uses the theory of ordinal numbers and the full power of the axioms of choice and replacement. Cardinal assignments do need the full axiom of choice, if we want a decent cardinal arithmetic and an assignment for all sets.
Cardinal assignment without the axiom of choice
Formally, assuming the axiom of choice, cardinality of a set X is the least ordinal α such that there is a bijection between X and α. This definition is known as the von Neumann cardinal assignment. If the axiom of choice is not assumed we need to do something different. The oldest definition of the cardinality of a set X (implicit in Cantor and explicit in Frege and Principia Mathematica) is as the set of all sets which are equinumerous with X: this does not work in ZFC or other related systems of axiomatic set theory because this collection is too large to be a set, but it does work in type theory and in New Foundations and related systems. However, if we restrict from this class to those equinumerous with X that have the least rank, then it will work (this is a trick due to Dana Scott: it works because the collection of objects with any given rank is a set).
References
- Moschovakis, Yiannis N. Notes on Set Theory. New York: Springer-Verlag, 1994.