Trichotomy (mathematics): Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Zorglub x
m xor does not appear in the equation
 
No edit summary
Line 1: Line 1:
Apart from the Clash of [http://Photobucket.com/images/Clans+hack Clans hack] tool; there might be also hack tools for the other games. People young and old can check out everyone hacks and obtain dozens of which they need. It is sure the player will have lost at fun once they feature the hack tool available.<br><br>As explained in the extremely Clash of Clans' Group Wars overview, anniversary alliance war is breach ascending into a couple phases: Alertness Day and Sports Day. Anniversary the look lasts 24 hours as well means that you will often accomplish altered things.<br><br>clash of clans is a ideal game, which usually requires in order to build your personal village, discover warriors, raid assets and build your get clan and so on. there is a lot a lot very much to this video task and for every one of these you require jewels in order to really play, as you desire. If you loved this article and you would certainly such as to receive even more information regarding hack clash of clans [[http://circuspartypanama.com Read the Full Content]] kindly go to our own web site. Clash of Clans hack allows you to obtain as many jewels as you like. There is an unlimited regarding gems you could establish with all the Collide of Clans cheats there online, however you requires to be specific about the hyperlink you are using for the reason some of them exclusively waste materials your serious amounts of also dont get an individual anything more.<br><br>Assuming that you're playing a quest online, and you execute across another player what kind of person seems to be aggravating other players (or you, in particular) intentionally, won't take it personally. This is called "Griefing," and it's the gaming equivalent of Internet trolling. Griefers are mearly out for negative attention, and you give them all what they're looking for the if you interact together. Don't get emotionally put in in what's happening as simply try to ignore it.<br><br>Wait for game of the season editions of real titles. These usually come out per time of year or higher after all the initial headline, but consists of a lot of the particular down-loadable and extra happy which was released when steps once the first headline. These ball game titles supply a lot more bang for all of the buck.<br><br>Ought to you are the proud holder of an ANY compact device that runs forward iOS or android as a touchscreen tablet computer or a smart phone, then you definitely would have already been mindful of the revolution making use of place right now within the world of mobile digital game "The Clash Having to do with Clans", and you would want to be in demand concerning conflict of families free jewels compromise because other gems, elixir and platinum are needed seriously toward acquire every battle.<br><br>Now you have read this composition, you need to a great easier time locating as well as , loving video games in your lifetime. Notwithstanding your favored platform, from your cellphone to any own computer, playing and enjoying video gaming allow you to take the benefit of the worries of a new busy week get advise.
In [[set theory]], a '''regular cardinal''' is a  [[cardinal number]] that is equal to its own [[cofinality]]. So, crudely speaking, a regular cardinal is one which cannot be broken into a smaller collection of smaller parts.
 
If the axiom of choice holds (so that any cardinal number can be well-ordered), an infinite cardinal <math>\kappa</math> is regular if and only if it cannot be expressed as the cardinal sum of a set of cardinality less than <math>\kappa</math>, the elements of which are cardinals less than <math>\kappa</math>. (The situation is slightly more complicated in contexts where the [[axiom of choice]] might fail; in that case not all cardinals are necessarily the cardinalities of [[well-ordered]] sets. In that case, the above definition is restricted to well-orderable cardinals only.)
 
An infinite ordinal <math>\alpha</math> is regular [[if and only if]] it is a [[limit ordinal]] which is not the limit of a set of smaller ordinals which set has [[order type]] less than <math>\alpha</math>. A regular ordinal is always an [[initial ordinal]], though some initial ordinals are not regular.
 
Infinite well-ordered cardinals which are not regular are called '''singular cardinals'''. Finite cardinal numbers are typically not called regular or singular.
__NOTOC__
== Examples ==
 
The ordinals less than <math>\omega</math> are finite. A finite sequence of finite ordinals always has a finite maximum, so <math>\omega</math> cannot be the limit of any sequence of type less than <math>\omega</math> whose elements are ordinals less than <math>\omega</math>, and is therefore a regular ordinal. <math>\aleph_0</math> ([[aleph-null]]) is a regular cardinal because its initial ordinal, <math>\omega</math>, is regular. It can also be seen directly to be regular, as the cardinal sum of a finite number of finite cardinal numbers is itself finite.
 
<math>\omega+1</math> is the [[successor ordinal|next ordinal number]] greater than <math>\omega</math>. It is singular, since it is not a limit ordinal. <math>\omega+\omega</math> is the next limit ordinal after <math>\omega</math>. It can be written as the limit of the sequence <math>\omega</math>, <math>\omega+1</math>, <math>\omega+2</math>, <math>\omega+3</math>, and so on. This sequence has order type <math>\omega</math>, so <math>\omega+\omega</math> is the limit of a sequence of type less than <math>\omega+\omega</math> whose elements are ordinals less than <math>\omega+\omega</math>, therefore it is singular.
 
<math>\aleph_1</math> is the [[successor cardinal|next cardinal number]] greater than <math>\aleph_0</math>, so the cardinals less than <math>\aleph_1</math> are [[countable set|countable]] (finite or denumerable). Assuming the axiom of choice, the union of a countable set of countable sets is itself countable. So <math>\aleph_1</math> cannot be written as the sum of a countable set of countable cardinal numbers, and is regular.
 
<math>\aleph_\omega</math> is the next cardinal number after the sequence <math>\aleph_0</math>, <math>\aleph_1</math>, <math>\aleph_2</math>, <math>\aleph_3</math>, and so on. Its initial ordinal <math>\omega_\omega</math> is the limit of the sequence <math>\omega</math>, <math>\omega_1</math>, <math>\omega_2</math>, <math>\omega_3</math>, and so on, which has order type <math>\omega</math>, so <math>\omega_\omega</math> is singular, and so is <math>\aleph_\omega</math>. Assuming the axiom of choice, <math>\aleph_\omega</math> is the first infinite cardinal which is singular (the first infinite ''ordinal'' which is singular is <math>\omega+1</math>). Proving the existence of singular cardinals requires the [[axiom schema of replacement|axiom of replacement]], and in fact the inability to prove the existence of <math>\aleph_\omega</math> in [[Zermelo set theory]] is what led [[Adolf Abraham Halevi Fraenkel|Fraenkel]] to postulate this axiom.{{Citation needed|date=August 2011}}
 
== Properties ==
 
Uncountable [[limit cardinal]]s that are also regular are known as weakly [[inaccessible cardinals]].  They cannot be proved to exist within ZFC, though their existence is not known to be inconsistent with ZFC. Their existence is sometimes taken as an additional axiom.  Inaccessible cardinals are necessarily [[fixed point (mathematics)|fixed point]]s of the [[aleph number|aleph function]], though not all fixed points are regular.  For instance, the first fixed point is the limit of the <math>\omega</math>-sequence <math>\aleph_0, \aleph_{\aleph_0}, \aleph_{\aleph_{\aleph_0}}, ...</math> and is therefore singular.
 
If the [[axiom of choice]] holds, then every [[successor cardinal]] is regular.  Thus the regularity or singularity of most aleph numbers can be checked depending on whether the cardinal is a successor cardinal or a limit cardinal.  Some cardinal numbers cannot be proven to be equal to any particular aleph, for instance the [[cardinality of the continuum]], whose value in ZFC may be any uncountable cardinal of uncountable cofinality (see [[Easton's theorem]]). The [[continuum hypothesis]] postulates that the cardinality of the continuum is equal to <math>\aleph_1</math> which is regular.
 
Without the axiom of choice, there would be cardinal numbers which were not well-orderable. Moreover, the cardinal sum of an arbitrary collection could not be defined. Therefore only the [[aleph number]]s can meaningfully be called regular or singular cardinals. Furthermore, a successor aleph need not be regular. For instance, the union of a countable set of countable sets need not be countable. It is consistent with [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory|ZF]] that <math>\omega_1</math> be the limit of a countable sequence of countable ordinals as well as the set of real numbers is countable union of countable sets. Furthermore, it is consistent with ZF that every aleph bigger than <math>\aleph_0</math> is singular (a result proved by [[Moti Gitik]]).
 
== See also ==
* [[Inaccessible cardinal]]
 
== References ==
* {{aut|[[Herbert Enderton|Herbert B. Enderton]]}}, ''Elements of Set Theory'', ISBN 0-12-238440-7
* {{aut|[[Kenneth Kunen]]}}, ''Set Theory, An Introduction to Independence Proofs'', ISBN 0-444-85401-0
 
[[Category:Ordinal numbers]]
[[Category:Cardinal numbers]]

Revision as of 01:13, 31 December 2013

In set theory, a regular cardinal is a cardinal number that is equal to its own cofinality. So, crudely speaking, a regular cardinal is one which cannot be broken into a smaller collection of smaller parts.

If the axiom of choice holds (so that any cardinal number can be well-ordered), an infinite cardinal κ is regular if and only if it cannot be expressed as the cardinal sum of a set of cardinality less than κ, the elements of which are cardinals less than κ. (The situation is slightly more complicated in contexts where the axiom of choice might fail; in that case not all cardinals are necessarily the cardinalities of well-ordered sets. In that case, the above definition is restricted to well-orderable cardinals only.)

An infinite ordinal α is regular if and only if it is a limit ordinal which is not the limit of a set of smaller ordinals which set has order type less than α. A regular ordinal is always an initial ordinal, though some initial ordinals are not regular.

Infinite well-ordered cardinals which are not regular are called singular cardinals. Finite cardinal numbers are typically not called regular or singular.

Examples

The ordinals less than ω are finite. A finite sequence of finite ordinals always has a finite maximum, so ω cannot be the limit of any sequence of type less than ω whose elements are ordinals less than ω, and is therefore a regular ordinal. 0 (aleph-null) is a regular cardinal because its initial ordinal, ω, is regular. It can also be seen directly to be regular, as the cardinal sum of a finite number of finite cardinal numbers is itself finite.

ω+1 is the next ordinal number greater than ω. It is singular, since it is not a limit ordinal. ω+ω is the next limit ordinal after ω. It can be written as the limit of the sequence ω, ω+1, ω+2, ω+3, and so on. This sequence has order type ω, so ω+ω is the limit of a sequence of type less than ω+ω whose elements are ordinals less than ω+ω, therefore it is singular.

1 is the next cardinal number greater than 0, so the cardinals less than 1 are countable (finite or denumerable). Assuming the axiom of choice, the union of a countable set of countable sets is itself countable. So 1 cannot be written as the sum of a countable set of countable cardinal numbers, and is regular.

ω is the next cardinal number after the sequence 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on. Its initial ordinal ωω is the limit of the sequence ω, ω1, ω2, ω3, and so on, which has order type ω, so ωω is singular, and so is ω. Assuming the axiom of choice, ω is the first infinite cardinal which is singular (the first infinite ordinal which is singular is ω+1). Proving the existence of singular cardinals requires the axiom of replacement, and in fact the inability to prove the existence of ω in Zermelo set theory is what led Fraenkel to postulate this axiom.Potter or Ceramic Artist Truman Bedell from Rexton, has interests which include ceramics, best property developers in singapore developers in singapore and scrabble. Was especially enthused after visiting Alejandro de Humboldt National Park.

Properties

Uncountable limit cardinals that are also regular are known as weakly inaccessible cardinals. They cannot be proved to exist within ZFC, though their existence is not known to be inconsistent with ZFC. Their existence is sometimes taken as an additional axiom. Inaccessible cardinals are necessarily fixed points of the aleph function, though not all fixed points are regular. For instance, the first fixed point is the limit of the ω-sequence 0,0,0,... and is therefore singular.

If the axiom of choice holds, then every successor cardinal is regular. Thus the regularity or singularity of most aleph numbers can be checked depending on whether the cardinal is a successor cardinal or a limit cardinal. Some cardinal numbers cannot be proven to be equal to any particular aleph, for instance the cardinality of the continuum, whose value in ZFC may be any uncountable cardinal of uncountable cofinality (see Easton's theorem). The continuum hypothesis postulates that the cardinality of the continuum is equal to 1 which is regular.

Without the axiom of choice, there would be cardinal numbers which were not well-orderable. Moreover, the cardinal sum of an arbitrary collection could not be defined. Therefore only the aleph numbers can meaningfully be called regular or singular cardinals. Furthermore, a successor aleph need not be regular. For instance, the union of a countable set of countable sets need not be countable. It is consistent with ZF that ω1 be the limit of a countable sequence of countable ordinals as well as the set of real numbers is countable union of countable sets. Furthermore, it is consistent with ZF that every aleph bigger than 0 is singular (a result proved by Moti Gitik).

See also

References

  • Template:Aut, Elements of Set Theory, ISBN 0-12-238440-7
  • Template:Aut, Set Theory, An Introduction to Independence Proofs, ISBN 0-444-85401-0