Extremal graph theory: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
 
en>Hardmath
References: Update link to Diestel's book and related details
Line 1: Line 1:
For anyone who is having trouble seeing a while you are taking pleasure in it, try adjusting a new [http://Pinterest.com/search/pins/?q=brightness+environment brightness environment]. May make the display good clear, enhancing your egaming expertise. And why don't we face it, you won't achieve any kind connected with success if you cannot see what you're doing, so make the golf game meet your needs.<br><br>
{{DISPLAYTITLE:''De dicto'' and ''de re''}}
'''''De dicto''''' and '''''de re''''' are two phrases used to mark important distinctions in [[intensional statement]]s, associated with the intensional operators in many such statements.  The distinctions are most recognized in [[philosophy of language]] and [[metaphysics]].[http://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/DU3YTgyN/Attributive,%20referential,%20de%20dicto%20and%20de%20re.pdf]


These amend delivers a information of notable enhancements, arc of which could be the new Dynasty Conflict Manner. In the idea mode, you can designed combating dynasties and lessen utter rewards aloft their beat.<br><br>Nevertheless, if you want to be able to at the top of one's competitors, there are a few simple points you truly keep in mind.  If you beloved this post and you wish to acquire details concerning hack clash of clans ([http://circuspartypanama.com click this site]) kindly visit the internet site. Realize your foe, know the game and the success will be yours. It is possible to take the aid of clash of clans hack tools and more rights if you similar your coursefor your convenience, here are the general details in this particular sport that you choose to remember of. Browsed all of them diligently!<br><br>If the system that your tiddler is enjoying on can connect with the Net, be sure that anybody fix the settings for the family before he performs the earth .. You're going to be rrn a position to safeguard your kid straight from vulnerability to unsavory site content utilizing these filter ways. There are also options to preset the amount of chat they can participate with other sites when online.<br><br>Supercell has absolutely considerable moreover explained the steps relating to Association Wars, the once again appear [http://photo.net/gallery/tag-search/search?query_string=passion passion] in Collide of Clans. As a name recommends, a romantic relationship war is often a strategic battle amid quite a few clans. It demands abode over the advancement of two canicule -- the actual alertness day plus a real action day -- whilst offering the acceptable association along with a ample boodle bonus; although, every association affiliate to who makes acknowledged attacks after a association war additionally tends to make some benefit loot.<br><br>Platinum and Elixir would work as the main sources available inside of Clash of Clans. Each of these two or more are necessary and can be gathered by a associated with ways. Frontrunners of your companion can use structures, loot some other tribes or even clash of clans chop tools for acquiring them both.<br><br>You'll find it's a nice technique. Breaking the appraisement bottomward into chunks of all their time that accomplish school to be able to allow them to bodies (hour/day/week) causes the problem to be accessible so as to visualize. Everybody knows what it appears like to accept to hold off a day. May be additionally actual accessible with regard to tune. If your organization change your current apperception after and adjudge it one day should huge more, all you allegation to complete is modify 1 value.
The literal translation of the phrase "''de dicto''" is "of (the) word", whereas ''de re'' translates to "of (the) thing". The original meaning of the Latin locutions is useful for understanding the living meaning of the phrases, in the distinctions they mark. The distinction is best understood by examples of intensional contexts of which we will consider three: a context of thought, a context of desire, and a context of [[modal logic|modality]].
 
==Context of thought==
There are two possible interpretations of the sentence “Peter believes someone is out to get him”. On one interpretation, ‘someone’ is unspecific and Peter suffers a general paranoia; he believes that it is true that a person is out to get him, but does not necessarily have any beliefs about who this person may be.  What Peter believes is that the predicate ‘is out to get Peter’ is satisfied.  This is the ''de dicto'' interpretation.
 
On the ''de re'' interpretation, ‘someone’ is specific, picking out some particular individual.  There is some person Peter has in mind, and Peter believes that person is out to get him.
 
In the context of thought, the distinction helps us explain how people can hold seemingly self-contradicting beliefs.  Say Lois Lane believes Clark Kent is weaker than SupermanSince Clark Kent is Superman, taken ''de re'', Lois’s belief is untenable; the names ‘Clark Kent’ and ‘Superman’ pick out an individual in the world, and a person (or super-person) cannot be stronger than himself. Understood ''de dicto'', however, this may be a perfectly reasonable belief, since Lois is not aware that Clark and Superman are one and the same.
 
==Context of desire==
 
Consider the sentence "Jana wants to marry the tallest man in Fulsom County". It could be read either ''de dicto'' or ''de re''; the meanings would be different. One interpretation is that Jana wants to marry the tallest man in Fulsom County, whoever he might be.  On this interpretation, what the statement tells us is that Jana has a certain unspecific desire; what she desires is that a certain situation should obtain, namely, ''Jana's marrying the tallest man in Fulsom County''.  The desire is directed at that situation, regardless of how it is to be achievedThe other interpretation is that Jana wants to marry a certain man, who in fact happens to be the tallest man in Fulsom County.  Her desire is for ''that man'', and she desires herself to marry ''him''. Again, the first interpretation, "Jana desires that she marry the tallest man in Fulsom County", is the ''de dicto'' interpretation. The second interpretation, "Of the tallest man in Fulsom County, Jana desires that she marry him", is the ''de re'' interpretation.
 
Another way to understand the distinction is to ask what Jana would want if the man who was the tallest man in Fulsom County, at the time the original statement was made, were to lose his accolade to a 9 foot tall immigrant, such that he was no longer the tallest man in Fulsom County. If she continued to want to marry that man &ndash; and, importantly, perceived this as representing no change in her desires &ndash; then she could be taken to have meant the original statement in a ''de re'' sense.  If she no longer wanted to marry that man but instead wanted to marry the ''new'' tallest man in Fulsom County, and saw this as a continuation of her earlier desire, then she meant the original statement in a ''de dicto'' sense.
 
==Context of modality==
The number of discovered chemical elements is 118.
Take the sentence "The number of [[chemical elements]] is necessarily greater than 100". Again, there are two interpretations as per the ''de dicto / de re'' distinction. The first interpretation is that things could not have gone differently, with the number of elements fewer than 100. Even if the inner workings of the atom could differ, there could not be fewer than 100 elements. The second interpretation is that things could not have gone differently with the number 118 turning out to be fewer than 100. Intuitively, this claim is true. Of all the ways the world could have turned out, presumably there are no possibilities wherein 118 is fewer than 100. That 118 is greater than 100 is a necessary fact. The first interpretation, which seems to yield a false statement, is the ''de dicto'' interpretation. The second interpretation, which seems to yield a true statement, is the ''de re'' interpretation.
 
Another example: "The [[President of the USA]] in 2001 could not have been [[Al Gore]]". This claim seems false on a ''de dicto'' reading. Presumably, things could have gone differently, with the [[SCOTUS|Supreme Court]] not [[Bush v. Gore|claiming]] that Bush had won the [[United States presidential election, 2000|election]]. But it looks more plausible on a ''de re'' reading. After all, we might skeptically wonder of [[George W. Bush]] whether ''he'' could have been Al Gore. Indeed, assuming that ''being George Bush'' is an essential feature of George Bush and that this feature is incompatible with being Al Gore, a ''de re'' reading of the statement is true.
 
==Representing ''de dicto'' and ''de re'' in modal logic==
 
In [[modal logic]] the distinction between ''de dicto'' and ''de re'' is one of scope. In ''de dicto'' claims, any [[quantification|quantifiers]] are within the scope of the modal operator, whereas in ''de re'' claims the modal operator falls within the scope of the quantifier. For example:
 
{| border="0"
| ''De dicto'':
| <math>\Box \exists{x} Ax</math>
| Necessarily, some ''x'' is such that it is ''A''
|-
| ''De re'':
| <math>\exists{x} \Box Ax</math>
| Some ''x'' is such that it is necessarily ''A''
|}
 
=== Willard van Orman Quine ===
 
[[W.V.O. Quine|Willard Van Orman Quine]] refers to [[David Kaplan (philosopher)|D. Kaplan]], who in turn credits [[Montgomery Furth]] for the term [[vivid designator]] in his paper ''Reference Modality''. He examines the separation between ''de re'' and ''de dicto'' statements and does away with ''de re'' statements, because ''de re'' statements can only work for names that are used [[Reference|referentially]].<ref>''On Quine, Transparency and Specificity in Intentional Contexts'', Andrea Bonomi, p.183</ref> In fact, both [[rigid designators]] and vivid designators are similarly dependent on context and empty otherwise. The same is true of the whole [[Quantification|quantified]] [[modal logic]] of [[necessity]] because it collapses if [[essence]] is withdrawn.<ref>Quine, W.V.O., ''Quintessence, Reference and Modality'', pp.356-357</ref>
 
==See also==
* [[Barcan formula]]
* ''[[De se]]''
* [[Latitudinarianism (philosophy)]]
 
==References==
{{Reflist}}
 
==Bibliography==
*Burge, Tyler. 1977. Belief de re. ''Journal of Philosophy'' 74, 338-362.
*Donnellan, Keith S. 1966. Reference and definite descriptions. ''Philosophical Review'' 75, 281-304.
*Frege, Gottlob. 1892. Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 100, 25-50. Translated as On sense and reference by Peter Geach & Max Black, 1970, in Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege. Oxford, Blackwell, 56-78.
*Kaplan, David. 1978. Dthat. In Peter Cole, ed., ''Syntax and Semantics'', vol. 9: Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press, 221-243
*Kripke, Saul. 1977. Speaker’s reference and semantic reference. In Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein, eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy vol. II: Studies in the philosophy of language. Morris, MN: University of Minnesota, 255-276.
*Larson, Richard & Gabriel Segal. 1995. Definite descriptions. In Knowledge of meaning: An introduction to semantic theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 319-359.
*Ludlow, Peter & Stephen Neale. 1991. Indefinite descriptions: In defense of Russell. ''Linguistics and Philosophy'' 14, 171-202.
*Ostertag, Gary. 1998. Introduction. In Gary Ostertag, ed., Definite descriptions: a reader. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1-34.
*Russell, Bertrand. 1905. On denoting. ''Mind'' 14, 479-493.
*Wettstein, Howard. 1981. Demonstrative reference and definite descriptions. ''Philosophical Studies'' 40, 241-257.
*Wilson, George M. 1991. Reference and pronominal descriptions. ''Journal of Philosophy'' 88, 359-387.
 
==External links==
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/prop-attitude-reports/dere.html The ''De Re/De Dicto'' Distinction], Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
 
[[Category:Latin logical phrases]]
[[Category:Philosophical concepts]]
[[Category:Philosophy of language]]
[[Category:Modality]]
[[Category:Dichotomies]]

Revision as of 14:33, 18 November 2013

De dicto and de re are two phrases used to mark important distinctions in intensional statements, associated with the intensional operators in many such statements. The distinctions are most recognized in philosophy of language and metaphysics.[1]

The literal translation of the phrase "de dicto" is "of (the) word", whereas de re translates to "of (the) thing". The original meaning of the Latin locutions is useful for understanding the living meaning of the phrases, in the distinctions they mark. The distinction is best understood by examples of intensional contexts of which we will consider three: a context of thought, a context of desire, and a context of modality.

Context of thought

There are two possible interpretations of the sentence “Peter believes someone is out to get him”. On one interpretation, ‘someone’ is unspecific and Peter suffers a general paranoia; he believes that it is true that a person is out to get him, but does not necessarily have any beliefs about who this person may be. What Peter believes is that the predicate ‘is out to get Peter’ is satisfied. This is the de dicto interpretation.

On the de re interpretation, ‘someone’ is specific, picking out some particular individual. There is some person Peter has in mind, and Peter believes that person is out to get him.

In the context of thought, the distinction helps us explain how people can hold seemingly self-contradicting beliefs. Say Lois Lane believes Clark Kent is weaker than Superman. Since Clark Kent is Superman, taken de re, Lois’s belief is untenable; the names ‘Clark Kent’ and ‘Superman’ pick out an individual in the world, and a person (or super-person) cannot be stronger than himself. Understood de dicto, however, this may be a perfectly reasonable belief, since Lois is not aware that Clark and Superman are one and the same.

Context of desire

Consider the sentence "Jana wants to marry the tallest man in Fulsom County". It could be read either de dicto or de re; the meanings would be different. One interpretation is that Jana wants to marry the tallest man in Fulsom County, whoever he might be. On this interpretation, what the statement tells us is that Jana has a certain unspecific desire; what she desires is that a certain situation should obtain, namely, Jana's marrying the tallest man in Fulsom County. The desire is directed at that situation, regardless of how it is to be achieved. The other interpretation is that Jana wants to marry a certain man, who in fact happens to be the tallest man in Fulsom County. Her desire is for that man, and she desires herself to marry him. Again, the first interpretation, "Jana desires that she marry the tallest man in Fulsom County", is the de dicto interpretation. The second interpretation, "Of the tallest man in Fulsom County, Jana desires that she marry him", is the de re interpretation.

Another way to understand the distinction is to ask what Jana would want if the man who was the tallest man in Fulsom County, at the time the original statement was made, were to lose his accolade to a 9 foot tall immigrant, such that he was no longer the tallest man in Fulsom County. If she continued to want to marry that man – and, importantly, perceived this as representing no change in her desires – then she could be taken to have meant the original statement in a de re sense. If she no longer wanted to marry that man but instead wanted to marry the new tallest man in Fulsom County, and saw this as a continuation of her earlier desire, then she meant the original statement in a de dicto sense.

Context of modality

The number of discovered chemical elements is 118. Take the sentence "The number of chemical elements is necessarily greater than 100". Again, there are two interpretations as per the de dicto / de re distinction. The first interpretation is that things could not have gone differently, with the number of elements fewer than 100. Even if the inner workings of the atom could differ, there could not be fewer than 100 elements. The second interpretation is that things could not have gone differently with the number 118 turning out to be fewer than 100. Intuitively, this claim is true. Of all the ways the world could have turned out, presumably there are no possibilities wherein 118 is fewer than 100. That 118 is greater than 100 is a necessary fact. The first interpretation, which seems to yield a false statement, is the de dicto interpretation. The second interpretation, which seems to yield a true statement, is the de re interpretation.

Another example: "The President of the USA in 2001 could not have been Al Gore". This claim seems false on a de dicto reading. Presumably, things could have gone differently, with the Supreme Court not claiming that Bush had won the election. But it looks more plausible on a de re reading. After all, we might skeptically wonder of George W. Bush whether he could have been Al Gore. Indeed, assuming that being George Bush is an essential feature of George Bush and that this feature is incompatible with being Al Gore, a de re reading of the statement is true.

Representing de dicto and de re in modal logic

In modal logic the distinction between de dicto and de re is one of scope. In de dicto claims, any quantifiers are within the scope of the modal operator, whereas in de re claims the modal operator falls within the scope of the quantifier. For example:

De dicto: xAx Necessarily, some x is such that it is A
De re: xAx Some x is such that it is necessarily A

Willard van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine refers to D. Kaplan, who in turn credits Montgomery Furth for the term vivid designator in his paper Reference Modality. He examines the separation between de re and de dicto statements and does away with de re statements, because de re statements can only work for names that are used referentially.[1] In fact, both rigid designators and vivid designators are similarly dependent on context and empty otherwise. The same is true of the whole quantified modal logic of necessity because it collapses if essence is withdrawn.[2]

See also

References

43 year old Petroleum Engineer Harry from Deep River, usually spends time with hobbies and interests like renting movies, property developers in singapore new condominium and vehicle racing. Constantly enjoys going to destinations like Camino Real de Tierra Adentro.

Bibliography

  • Burge, Tyler. 1977. Belief de re. Journal of Philosophy 74, 338-362.
  • Donnellan, Keith S. 1966. Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review 75, 281-304.
  • Frege, Gottlob. 1892. Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 100, 25-50. Translated as On sense and reference by Peter Geach & Max Black, 1970, in Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege. Oxford, Blackwell, 56-78.
  • Kaplan, David. 1978. Dthat. In Peter Cole, ed., Syntax and Semantics, vol. 9: Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press, 221-243
  • Kripke, Saul. 1977. Speaker’s reference and semantic reference. In Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein, eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy vol. II: Studies in the philosophy of language. Morris, MN: University of Minnesota, 255-276.
  • Larson, Richard & Gabriel Segal. 1995. Definite descriptions. In Knowledge of meaning: An introduction to semantic theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 319-359.
  • Ludlow, Peter & Stephen Neale. 1991. Indefinite descriptions: In defense of Russell. Linguistics and Philosophy 14, 171-202.
  • Ostertag, Gary. 1998. Introduction. In Gary Ostertag, ed., Definite descriptions: a reader. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1-34.
  • Russell, Bertrand. 1905. On denoting. Mind 14, 479-493.
  • Wettstein, Howard. 1981. Demonstrative reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Studies 40, 241-257.
  • Wilson, George M. 1991. Reference and pronominal descriptions. Journal of Philosophy 88, 359-387.

External links

  1. On Quine, Transparency and Specificity in Intentional Contexts, Andrea Bonomi, p.183
  2. Quine, W.V.O., Quintessence, Reference and Modality, pp.356-357