Modus ponens: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>MRG90
No edit summary
 
Line 1: Line 1:
Well, in the first place, theres your competition issue. For many years, wire was the only path to g... <br><br>Satellite TV has become a highly popular option in comparison to cable TV since its more reliable, less-expensive and provides you with a good amount of channels and net-works including national and international, specially-broadcasted sports, satellite music stations and more. Why satellite TV is cheaper than cable, but did you ever wonder, with all its benefits? <br><br>Well, to begin with, theres the competition factor. For quite some time, cable was the only path to get clear reception and access local programming programs with no use of rabbit ears. Clicking [http://www.localcablesales.com/comcast-xfinity-internet/seattle-wa/ open in a new browser] likely provides tips you could tell your friend. And then obviously, with the addition of the increasing quantity of broadcasting systems offered through cable, it gave people an abundance of choices for both movie and TELEVISION viewing. But along comes satellite and it has to compete with something which has developed a trust-worthy and reliable position in the publics eye. So in an effort to cultivate their business and customer base, and not only take on, but lure people away from the cable organizations and keep those clients as well, the satellite providers offered lower monthly pricing choices as well as free installation in many cases. <br><br>Therefore, with lower monthly premiums, a heightened quantity of channels, special event broadcasts not available through the cable networks, music areas, movie channels and other special features that cable doesnt or didnt, at the time, offer, many people started switching over from their cable TV firms to satellite service. <br><br>Still another fascinating feature with satellite TV compared to cable TV, is that the satellite TV companies customer care representatives can be found 24-hours a day, 7-days a week, unlike the cable companies who only work the standard Monday through Friday, 9-5 work week - and often a half-a-day o-n Saturday. That can be extremely frustrating when someone needs assistance with set-up or has general concerns after [https://Www.google.com/search?hl=en&gl=us&tbm=nws&q=normal+business&btnI=lucky normal business] hours and/or around the weekend which will be when many people actually have the full time to contact customer service. <br><br>Naturally, satellite TV reception can also be much better and more trustworthy than cable TV which has considerably helped in sustaining its growth and popularity amongst the viewing public. And then theres also the cost with respect to the satellite company businesses regarding service and maintenance charges. Because there are no poles to climb, and so on theres no need to send a specialist. If satellite company were be interrupted in a whole area which will be very rare and might only occur in cases of extreme weather every thing could be set either on the element of the client altering the bowl themselves, or via a online network at the satellite companys office that accesses the specific satellite in space and adjusts/addresses any signal issues. <br><br>The important thing is that the satellite TELEVISION service providers are well aware of most of this and additionally know compared to cable companies do that they rank higher in customer service. So, over all, from its beginning through present, theyve accepted that theres no need to demand or increase their rates in order to take on the cable companies..<br><br>Here's more information regarding [http://evasivedairy4709.soup.io online health insurance] check out our own page.
{{Use dmy dates|date=July 2012}}{{Italic title}}{{Transformation rules}}
 
In [[propositional calculus|propositional logic]], '''''modus tollens'''''<ref>University of North Carolina, Philosophy Department, [http://www.philosophy.uncc.edu/mleldrid/Logic/logiglos.html#modustollens Logic Glossary]. Accessdate on 31 October 2007.</ref><ref>Copi and Cohen</ref><ref>Hurley</ref><ref>Moore and Parker</ref> (or '''''modus tollendo tollens''''' and also '''denying the consequent''')<ref>Sanford, David Hawley. 2003. ''If P, Then Q: Conditionals and the Foundations of Reasoning''. London, UK: Routledge: 39 "[Modus] tollens is always an abbreviation for modus tollendo tollens, the mood that by denying denies."</ref> ([[Latin language|Latin]] for "the way that denies by denying")<ref>Stone, Jon R. 1996. ''Latin for the Illiterati: Exorcizing the Ghosts of a Dead Language''. London, UK: Routledge: 60.</ref> is a [[validity|valid]] [[argument form]] and a [[rule of inference]].
 
The first to explicitly state the argument form ''modus tollens'' were the Stoics.<ref>[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-ancient/#Sto "Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: ''Ancient Logic: The Stoics''"]</ref>
 
The inference rule ''modus tollens'', also known as the '''law of contrapositive''', validates the [[inference]] from <math>P</math> implies <math>Q</math> and the contradictory of <math>Q</math>, to the contradictory of <math>P</math>.
 
The ''modus tollens'' rule can be stated formally as:
 
:<math>\frac{P \to Q, \neg Q}{\therefore \neg P}</math>
 
where <math>P \to Q</math> stands for "P implies Q", <math>\neg Q</math> stands for "it is not the case that Q" (or in brief "not Q"). Then, whenever "<math>P \to Q</math>" and "<math>\neg Q</math>" each appear by themselves as a line of a [[formal proof|proof]], "<math>\neg P</math>" can validly be placed on a subsequent line. The history of the inference rule ''modus tollens''  goes back to antiquity.<ref>[[Susanne Bobzien]] (2002). [http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/156852802321016541 "The Development of Modus Ponens in Antiquity"], ''Phronesis'' 47.</ref>
 
''Modus tollens'' is closely related to ''[[modus ponens]]''. There are two similar, but [[fallacy|invalid, forms of argument]]: [[affirming the consequent]] and [[denying the antecedent]].
 
== Formal notation ==
The ''modus tollens'' rule may be written in [[sequent]] notation:
 
:<math>P\to Q, \neg Q \vdash \neg P</math>
 
where <math>\vdash</math> is a [[metalogic]]al symbol meaning that <math>\neg P</math> is a [[logical consequence|syntactic consequence]] of <math>P \to Q</math> and <math>\neg Q</math> in some [[formal system|logical system]];
 
or as the statement of a functional [[Tautology (logic)|tautology]] or [[theorem]] of propositional logic:
 
:<math>((P \to Q) \and \neg Q) \to \neg P</math>
 
where <math>P</math>, and <math>Q</math> are propositions expressed in some logical system;
 
or including assumptions:
:<math>\frac{\Gamma \vdash P\to Q ~~~ \Gamma \vdash\neg Q}{\Gamma \vdash \neg P}</math>
though since the rule does not change the set of assumptions, this is not strictly necessary.
 
More complex rewritings involving ''modus tollens'' are often seen, for instance in [[set theory]]:
 
:<math>P\subseteq Q</math>
:<math>x\notin Q</math>
:<math>\therefore x\notin P</math>
("P is a subset of Q. x is not in Q. Therefore, x is not in P.")
 
Also in first-order [[predicate logic]]:
 
:<math>\forall x:~P(x) \to Q(x)</math>
:<math>\exists x:~\neg Q(x)</math>
:<math>\therefore \exists x:~\neg P(x)</math>
("For all x if x is P then x is Q. There exists some x that is not Q. Therefore, there exists some x that is not P.")
 
Strictly speaking these are not instances of ''modus tollens'', but they may be derived using ''modus tollens'' using a few extra steps.
 
== Explanation ==
The argument has two premises. The first premise is a conditional or "if-then" statement, for example that if P then Q. The second premise is that it is not the case that Q . From these two premises, it can be logically concluded that it is not the case that P.
 
Consider an example:
:If the watch-dog detects an intruder, the watch-dog will bark.
:The watch-dog did not bark
:Therefore, no intruder was detected by the watch-dog.
 
Supposing that the premises are both true (the dog will bark if it detects an intruder, and does indeed not bark), it follows that no intruder has been detected. This is a valid argument since it is not possible for the conclusion to be false if the premises are true. (It is conceivable that there may have been an intruder that the dog did not detect, but that does not invalidate the argument; the first premise goes "if the watch-dog '''detects''' an intruder." The thing of importance is that the dog detects or doesn't detect an intruder, not if there is one.)
 
Another example:
:If I am the axe murderer, then I can use an axe.
:I cannot use an axe.
:Therefore, I am not the axe murderer.
 
== Relation to ''modus ponens'' ==
Every use of ''modus tollens'' can be converted to a use of ''modus ponens'' and one use of [[transposition (logic)|transposition]] to the premise which is a material implication. For example:
 
:If P, then Q. (premise -- material implication)
:If not Q , then not P. (derived by transposition)
:Not Q . (premise)
:Therefore, not  P. (derived by ''modus ponens'')
 
Likewise, every use of ''modus ponens'' can be converted to a use of ''modus tollens'' and transposition.
 
== Justification via truth table ==
The validity of ''modus tollens'' can be clearly demonstrated through a [[truth table]].
 
{| class="wikitable" style="margin: 0 auto; text-align:center; width:45%"
|-
! style="width:15%" | p
! style="width:15%" | q
! style="width:15%" | p → q
|-
| T || T || T
|-
| T || F || F
|-
| F || T || T
|-
| F || F || T
|}
 
In instances of ''modus tollens'' we assume as premises that p → q is true and q is false. There is only one line of the truth table—the fourth line—which satisfies these two conditions. In this line, p is false. Therefore, in every instance in which p → q is true and q is false, p must also be false.
 
==Formal Proof==
 
===Via Disjunctive syllogism===
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:lightcyan; font-weight:bold; text-align:center; width:45%"
|+ ''' '''
|- style="background:paleturquoise"
! style="width:5%" | ''Step''
! style="width:15%" | ''Proposition''
! style="width:25%" | ''Derivation''
|-
| 1 || <math>P\rightarrow Q</math> || Given
|-
| 2 || <math>\neg Q</math> || Given
|-
| 3 || <math>\neg P\or Q</math> || [[Material implication (rule of inference)|Material implication]] (1)
|-
| 4 || <math>\neg P</math> || [[Disjunctive syllogism]] (2,3)
|}
 
===Via ''Reductio ad absurdum''===
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:lightcyan; font-weight:bold; text-align:center; width:45%"
|+ ''' '''
|- style="background:paleturquoise"
! style="width:5%" | ''Step''
! style="width:15%" | ''Proposition''
! style="width:30%" | ''Derivation''
|-
| 1 || <math>P\rightarrow Q</math> || Given
|-
| 2 || <math>\neg Q</math> || Given
|-
| 3 || <math>P</math> || Assumption
|-
| 4 || <math>Q</math> || [[Modus ponens]] (1,3)
|-
| 5 || <math>Q \and \neg Q</math> || [[Conjunction introduction]] (2,4)
|-
| 6 || <math>\neg P</math> || ''[[Reductio ad absurdum]]'' (3,5)
|}
 
== See also ==
* [[Evidence of absence]]
* ''[[Non sequitur (logic)|Non sequitur]]''
* [[Proof by contradiction]]
* [[Proof by contrapositive]]
 
== Notes ==
{{reflist}}
 
== External links ==
* ''[http://mathworld.wolfram.com/ModusTollens.html Modus Tollens]'' at Wolfram MathWorld
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Modus Tollens}}
[[Category:Classical logic]]
[[Category:Rules of inference]]
[[Category:Latin logical phrases]]
[[Category:Theorems in propositional logic]]
 
[[fr:Modus tollens]]

Revision as of 08:34, 21 May 2013

30 year-old Entertainer or Range Artist Wesley from Drumheller, really loves vehicle, property developers properties for sale in singapore singapore and horse racing. Finds inspiration by traveling to Works of Antoni Gaudí.Template:Italic titleTemplate:Transformation rules

In propositional logic, modus tollens[1][2][3][4] (or modus tollendo tollens and also denying the consequent)[5] (Latin for "the way that denies by denying")[6] is a valid argument form and a rule of inference.

The first to explicitly state the argument form modus tollens were the Stoics.[7]

The inference rule modus tollens, also known as the law of contrapositive, validates the inference from implies and the contradictory of , to the contradictory of .

The modus tollens rule can be stated formally as:

where stands for "P implies Q", stands for "it is not the case that Q" (or in brief "not Q"). Then, whenever "" and "" each appear by themselves as a line of a proof, "" can validly be placed on a subsequent line. The history of the inference rule modus tollens goes back to antiquity.[8]

Modus tollens is closely related to modus ponens. There are two similar, but invalid, forms of argument: affirming the consequent and denying the antecedent.

Formal notation

The modus tollens rule may be written in sequent notation:

where is a metalogical symbol meaning that is a syntactic consequence of and in some logical system;

or as the statement of a functional tautology or theorem of propositional logic:

where , and are propositions expressed in some logical system;

or including assumptions:

though since the rule does not change the set of assumptions, this is not strictly necessary.

More complex rewritings involving modus tollens are often seen, for instance in set theory:

("P is a subset of Q. x is not in Q. Therefore, x is not in P.")

Also in first-order predicate logic:

("For all x if x is P then x is Q. There exists some x that is not Q. Therefore, there exists some x that is not P.")

Strictly speaking these are not instances of modus tollens, but they may be derived using modus tollens using a few extra steps.

Explanation

The argument has two premises. The first premise is a conditional or "if-then" statement, for example that if P then Q. The second premise is that it is not the case that Q . From these two premises, it can be logically concluded that it is not the case that P.

Consider an example:

If the watch-dog detects an intruder, the watch-dog will bark.
The watch-dog did not bark
Therefore, no intruder was detected by the watch-dog.

Supposing that the premises are both true (the dog will bark if it detects an intruder, and does indeed not bark), it follows that no intruder has been detected. This is a valid argument since it is not possible for the conclusion to be false if the premises are true. (It is conceivable that there may have been an intruder that the dog did not detect, but that does not invalidate the argument; the first premise goes "if the watch-dog detects an intruder." The thing of importance is that the dog detects or doesn't detect an intruder, not if there is one.)

Another example:

If I am the axe murderer, then I can use an axe.
I cannot use an axe.
Therefore, I am not the axe murderer.

Relation to modus ponens

Every use of modus tollens can be converted to a use of modus ponens and one use of transposition to the premise which is a material implication. For example:

If P, then Q. (premise -- material implication)
If not Q , then not P. (derived by transposition)
Not Q . (premise)
Therefore, not P. (derived by modus ponens)

Likewise, every use of modus ponens can be converted to a use of modus tollens and transposition.

Justification via truth table

The validity of modus tollens can be clearly demonstrated through a truth table.

p q p → q
T T T
T F F
F T T
F F T

In instances of modus tollens we assume as premises that p → q is true and q is false. There is only one line of the truth table—the fourth line—which satisfies these two conditions. In this line, p is false. Therefore, in every instance in which p → q is true and q is false, p must also be false.

Formal Proof

Via Disjunctive syllogism

Step Proposition Derivation
1 Given
2 Given
3 Material implication (1)
4 Disjunctive syllogism (2,3)

Via Reductio ad absurdum

Step Proposition Derivation
1 Given
2 Given
3 Assumption
4 Modus ponens (1,3)
5 Conjunction introduction (2,4)
6 Reductio ad absurdum (3,5)

See also

Notes

43 year old Petroleum Engineer Harry from Deep River, usually spends time with hobbies and interests like renting movies, property developers in singapore new condominium and vehicle racing. Constantly enjoys going to destinations like Camino Real de Tierra Adentro.

External links

fr:Modus tollens

  1. University of North Carolina, Philosophy Department, Logic Glossary. Accessdate on 31 October 2007.
  2. Copi and Cohen
  3. Hurley
  4. Moore and Parker
  5. Sanford, David Hawley. 2003. If P, Then Q: Conditionals and the Foundations of Reasoning. London, UK: Routledge: 39 "[Modus] tollens is always an abbreviation for modus tollendo tollens, the mood that by denying denies."
  6. Stone, Jon R. 1996. Latin for the Illiterati: Exorcizing the Ghosts of a Dead Language. London, UK: Routledge: 60.
  7. "Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Ancient Logic: The Stoics"
  8. Susanne Bobzien (2002). "The Development of Modus Ponens in Antiquity", Phronesis 47.