Moment distribution method: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>ProfessorXY
 
Line 1: Line 1:
I would like to introduce myself to you, I am Jayson Simcox but I don't like when individuals [http://checkmates.co.za/index.php?do=/profile-56347/info/ best psychic] use my full name. Some time ago he chose to reside in North Carolina and he doesn't plan on altering it. One of the extremely very best things in the globe for him is performing ballet and he'll be starting some thing else along with it. Distributing manufacturing is how he tends to make a living.<br><br>My web page - [http://myfusionprofits.com/groups/find-out-about-self-improvement-tips-here/ accurate psychic predictions] ([http://c045.danah.co.kr/home/index.php?document_srl=1356970&mid=qna c045.danah.co.kr])
'''Forcing''' in [[recursion theory]] is a modification of [[Paul Cohen (mathematician)|Paul Cohen's]] original [[set theory|set theoretic]] technique of [[forcing (set theory)|forcing]] to deal with the effective concerns in [[recursion theory]].  Conceptually the two techniques are quite similar, in both one attempts to build [[generic set|generic]] objects (intuitively objects that are somehow 'typical') by meeting dense sets.  Also both techniques are elegantly described as a relation (customarily denoted <math>\Vdash</math>) between 'conditions' and sentences.  However, where set theoretic forcing is usually interested in creating objects that meet every dense set of conditions in the ground model, recursion theoretic forcing only aims to meet dense sets that are arithmetically or hyperarithmetically definable.  Therefore some of the more difficult machinery used in set theoretic forcing can be eliminated or substantially simplified when defining forcing in recursion theory. But while the machinery may be somewhat different recursion theoretic and set theoretic forcing are properly regarded as an application of the same technique to different classes of formulas.
 
==Terminology==
 
In this article we use the following terminology. 
 
;real: an element of <math>2^\omega</math>.  In other words a function that maps each integer to either 0 or 1.
;string:  an element of <math>2^{<\omega}</math>.  In other words a finite approximation to a real.
 
; notion of forcing : A notion of forcing is a set <math>P</math> and a [[partial order]] on <math>P</math>, <math>\succ_{P}</math> with a ''greatest element'' <math>0_{P}</math>.
 
;condition: An element in a notion of forcing. We say a condition <math>p</math> is stronger than a condition <math>q</math> just when <math>q \succ_P p</math>.
 
;<math>p\mid q</math>: Given conditions <math>p,q</math> say that <math>p</math> and <math>q</math> are incompatible if there is no condition <math>r</math> with <math> p \succ_P r</math> and <math>q \succ_P r</math>.  <math>p</math> is compatible with <math>q</math> if they are not incompatible. <!-- Sometimes we will use '''consistent''' as a synonym for compatible. -->
 
;Filter : A subset <math>F</math> of a notion of forcing <math>P</math> is a filter if <math>p,q \in F \implies p \nmid q</math> and <math>p \in F \land q \succ_P p \implies q \in F</math>.  In other words a filter is a compatible set of conditions closed under weakening of conditions.
 
;Ultrafilter : A maximal filter, i.e., <math>F</math> is an ultrafilter if <math>F</math> is a filter and there is no filter <math>F'</math> properly containing <math>F</math>
 
; Cohen forcing: The notion of forcing <math>C</math> where conditions are elements of <math>2^{<\omega}</math> and <math>(\tau \succ_C \sigma \iff \sigma \supset \tau</math>)
 
Note that for Cohen forcing <math>\succ_{C}</math> is the '''reverse''' of the containment relation. This leads to an unfortunate notational confusion where some recursion theorists reverse the direction of the forcing partial order (exchanging <math>\succ_P</math> with <math>\prec_P</math>  which is more natural for Cohen forcing but is at odds with the notation used in set theory.
 
== Generic objects ==
 
The intuition behind forcing is that our conditions are finite approximations to some object we wish to build and that <math>\sigma</math> is stronger than <math>\tau</math> when <math>\sigma</math> agrees with everything <math>\tau</math> says about the object we are building and adds some information of its own. For instance in Cohen forcing the conditions can be viewed as finite approximations to a real and if <math>\tau \succ_C \sigma</math> then <math>\sigma</math> tells us the value of the real on more places.
 
In a moment we will define a relation <math>\sigma \Vdash_P \psi</math> (read <math>\sigma</math> forces <math>\psi</math>) that holds between conditions (elements of <math>P</math>) and sentences but first we need to explain the [[language (mathematics)]] that <math>\psi</math> is a sentence for. However, forcing is a technique not a definition and the language for <math>\psi</math> will depend on the application one has in mind and the choice of <math>P</math>.
 
The idea is that our language should express facts about the object we wish to build with our forcing construction.
 
== References ==
* Melvin Fitting (1981), ''Fundamentals of generalized recursion theory''.
* Piergiorgio Odifreddi (1999), ''Classical Recursion Theory'', v. 2.
 
[[Category:Computability theory]]

Revision as of 11:07, 10 January 2014

Forcing in recursion theory is a modification of Paul Cohen's original set theoretic technique of forcing to deal with the effective concerns in recursion theory. Conceptually the two techniques are quite similar, in both one attempts to build generic objects (intuitively objects that are somehow 'typical') by meeting dense sets. Also both techniques are elegantly described as a relation (customarily denoted ) between 'conditions' and sentences. However, where set theoretic forcing is usually interested in creating objects that meet every dense set of conditions in the ground model, recursion theoretic forcing only aims to meet dense sets that are arithmetically or hyperarithmetically definable. Therefore some of the more difficult machinery used in set theoretic forcing can be eliminated or substantially simplified when defining forcing in recursion theory. But while the machinery may be somewhat different recursion theoretic and set theoretic forcing are properly regarded as an application of the same technique to different classes of formulas.

Terminology

In this article we use the following terminology.

real
an element of . In other words a function that maps each integer to either 0 or 1.
string
an element of . In other words a finite approximation to a real.
notion of forcing
A notion of forcing is a set and a partial order on , with a greatest element .
condition
An element in a notion of forcing. We say a condition is stronger than a condition just when .
Given conditions say that and are incompatible if there is no condition with and . is compatible with if they are not incompatible.
Filter
A subset of a notion of forcing is a filter if and . In other words a filter is a compatible set of conditions closed under weakening of conditions.
Ultrafilter
A maximal filter, i.e., is an ultrafilter if is a filter and there is no filter properly containing
Cohen forcing
The notion of forcing where conditions are elements of and )

Note that for Cohen forcing is the reverse of the containment relation. This leads to an unfortunate notational confusion where some recursion theorists reverse the direction of the forcing partial order (exchanging with which is more natural for Cohen forcing but is at odds with the notation used in set theory.

Generic objects

The intuition behind forcing is that our conditions are finite approximations to some object we wish to build and that is stronger than when agrees with everything says about the object we are building and adds some information of its own. For instance in Cohen forcing the conditions can be viewed as finite approximations to a real and if then tells us the value of the real on more places.

In a moment we will define a relation (read forces ) that holds between conditions (elements of ) and sentences but first we need to explain the language (mathematics) that is a sentence for. However, forcing is a technique not a definition and the language for will depend on the application one has in mind and the choice of .

The idea is that our language should express facts about the object we wish to build with our forcing construction.

References

  • Melvin Fitting (1981), Fundamentals of generalized recursion theory.
  • Piergiorgio Odifreddi (1999), Classical Recursion Theory, v. 2.