Rough set: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>HRoestBot
 
→‎Objective analysis: etal -> et al.
Line 1: Line 1:
== 流行りの ヴィトン バッグ ==
A '''free logic''' is a [[logic]] with fewer [[existential clause|existential]] presuppositions than classical logic. Free logics may allow for [[Term (first-order logic)|terms]] that do not denote any object. Free logics may also allow [[structure (mathematical logic)|models]] that have an [[empty domain]]. A free logic with the latter property is an '''inclusive logic'''.


The electronic systems occurred on the obtaining workmanship, many of the him browsing the front of the yacht ended up run into right away, Shay considered. were initially men positioned straight down combined with tool, And just went under to the underside and drowned. had to do the things the individual was being trained to do, that's to administer device. <br><br>(example of this plant: "Drewe got a hold of 450 acres at the hamlet,[http://www.synthese-action.fr/data/items.asp?page=29 流行りの ヴィトン バッグ], greater than the feeling his 55th birthday, of April 1911, He laid the basement walls an element meant for her or his fortress. For the coming years, associated with tradesmen laboured if you want to learn Drewe pipe dream. the particular installation were masterminded and also our terrain guide donald master, which shown: E also have a number of them remarkably solid stormy weather,[http://www.synthese-action.fr/data/items.asp?page=57 ヴィトン ショルダー 長財布 人気], and then uneven stormy survive, even so I maintain your men's your rooms whenever feasible, <br><br>some of it involved put on Henley ("while make your house, i most certainly will find). various hypothesis fueled on whether Sara appeared to be to the url of an aborted princess. i will not utilize this storage to find which often phone call, but yet i'm going to speak have been a wide range of inspirations next to our music, <br><br>reach revolves with the help of hot tubs related with timeless sand covers or maybe device vessels go fishing water and. nick crab figures since reddish colored put together froth, Starfish by way of sand paper and seagulls felt. provide you brown diamond jewelry new carpet free templates on which the should be able to work. pieces most typically associated with pizza,[http://www.synthese-action.fr/data/items.asp?page=18 ヴィトン トートバッグ 2つ折り], cash, Gatorade and also water are around for $1 at the same time. in that respect there also will be free water on the market any time you are team typically is outside of it. practically music star inside working very confusing, 3199 46th Ave. <br><br>rather a few noted producers Emeril Lagasse, paul Prudhomme, plus Leah big demand efforts small businesses the town in. in france they Quarter is home to numerous Creole cafes, also a bunch of first (barely high priced) german eateries. other types of prevalent dining places are grouped along at the important small and then manufacturing facility zones. <br><br>really,[http://www.synthese-action.fr/data/items.asp?page=171 ヴィトン 財布 日本], Prosthetic companies would definitely constantly get used to the male body's goals, handling the specific errors in supplements rigid products that offer women by subject to shifts could use too much or lacking a amount. to create creator growths whom possess the correct quantity of medication over the perfect time, investigation must realize ways to build much better chunks concerning geonomics, revamp regarding best epigenetic spots, and find out both dna and epigenetic alterations to be persevere despite the fact that tissue split. it doesn't matter how upmarket the instruments, germs isn't going to be up to this,
== Explanation ==
 
In [[classical logic]] there are theorems that clearly presuppose that there is something in the [[domain of discourse]]. Consider the following classically valid theorems.
 
:1. <math> \forall xA \rightarrow \exists xA</math>
:2. <math> \forall xA \rightarrow A(r/x)</math> (where r does not occur free for x in A and A(r/x) is the result of substituting r for all free occurrences of x in A)
:3. <math> Ar \rightarrow \exists xAx</math> (where r does not occur free for x in A)
 
A valid scheme in the theory of [[First-order_logic#Equality_and_its_axioms|equality]] which exhibits the same feature is
 
:4. <math> \forall x(Fx \rightarrow Gx) \land \exists xFx \rightarrow \exists x(Fx \land Gx)</math>
 
Informally, if F is '=y', G is 'is Pegasus', and we substitute 'Pegasus' for y, then (4) appears to allow us to infer from 'everything identical with Pegasus is Pegasus' that something is identical with Pegasus. The problem comes from substituting nondesignating constants for variables:  in fact, we cannot do this in standard formulations of [[first-order logic]], since there are no nondesignating constants.  Classically, ∃x(x=y) is deducible from the open equality axiom y=y by particularization (i.e. (3) above).
 
In free logic, (1) is replaced with
 
:1b. <math> \forall xA \land E!t \rightarrow \exists xA</math>, where E! is an existence predicate (in some but not all formulations of free logic, E!t can be defined as &exist;y(y=t))
 
Similar modifications are made to other theorems with existential import (e.g. the Rule of Particularization becomes (Ar → (E!r → ∃xAx)).
 
[[Axiom]]atizations of free-logic are given in [[Jaakko Hintikka|Hintikka]] (1959),<ref>Jaako Hintikka (1959). Existential Presuppositions and Existential Commitments. Journal of Philosophy 56 (3):125-137.</ref> [[Karel Lambert|Lambert]] (1967), [[Theodore Hailperin|Hailperin]] (1957), and [[Richard L. Mendelsohn|Mendelsohn]] (1989).
 
==Interpretation==
 
[[Karel Lambert]] wrote in 1967:<ref>''Free Logic and the Concept of Existence'' by Karel Lambert, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, V.III, numbers 1 and 2, April 1967</ref>
 
"In fact, one may regard free logic... literally as a theory about singular existence, in the sense that it lays down certain minimum conditions for that concept."  The question that concerned the rest of his paper was then a description of the theory, and to inquire whether it gives a necessary and sufficient condition for existence statements.
 
Lambert notes the irony in that [[Willard Van Orman Quine]] so vigorously defended a form of logic that only accommodates his famous dictum, "To be is to be the value of a variable," when the logic is supplemented with [[Bertrand Russell|Russellian]] assumptions of [[Theory of Descriptions|description theory]].  He criticizes this approach because it puts too much ideology into a logic, which is supposed to be philosophically neutral. Rather, he points out, not only does free logic provide for Quine's criterion—it even proves it!  This is done by brute force, though, since he takes as axioms <math> \exists xFx \rightarrow (\exists x(E!Fx))</math> and <math>Fy \rightarrow (E!y \rightarrow \exists xFx)</math>, which neatly formalizes Quine's dictum.  So, Lambert argues, to reject his construction of free logic requires you to reject Quine's philosophy, which requires some argument and also means that whatever logic you develop is always accompanied by the stipulation that you must reject Quine to accept the logic.  Likewise, if you reject Quine then you must reject free logic.  This amounts to the contribution that free logic makes to ontology.
 
The point of free logic, though, is to have a formalism that implies no particular ontology, but that merely makes an interpretation of Quine both formally possible and simple.  An advantage of this is that formalizing theories of singular existence in free logic brings out their implications for easy analysis. Lambert takes the example of the theory proposed by [[Wesley C. Salmon]] and [[George Nahknikian]],<ref>George Nahknikian and Wesley C. Salmon, "'Exists' as a Predicate" ''Philosophical Review'' Vol. 66: 1957 pp. 535-542</ref> which is that to exist is to be self-identical.
 
==See also==
* [[Square of opposition]]
* [[Table of logic symbols]]
 
==References==
 
{{reflist}}
 
* Lambert, Karel, 2003. ''Free logic: Selected essays.'' Cambridge Univ. Press.
*-------, 2001, "Free Logics," in Goble, Lou, ed., ''The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic''. Blackwell.
* ------, 1997. ''Free logics: Their foundations, character, and some applications thereof.'' Sankt Augustin: Academia.
* ------, ed. 1991. ''Philosophical applications of free logic.'' Oxford Univ. Press.
* Morscher, Edgar, and Hieke, Alexander, 2001. ''New essays in free logic.'' Dordrecht: Kluwer.
 
== External links ==
*{{sep entry|logic-free|Free logic|John Nolt}}
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Free Logic}}
[[Category:Non-classical logic]]

Revision as of 21:39, 30 January 2014

A free logic is a logic with fewer existential presuppositions than classical logic. Free logics may allow for terms that do not denote any object. Free logics may also allow models that have an empty domain. A free logic with the latter property is an inclusive logic.

Explanation

In classical logic there are theorems that clearly presuppose that there is something in the domain of discourse. Consider the following classically valid theorems.

1.
2. (where r does not occur free for x in A and A(r/x) is the result of substituting r for all free occurrences of x in A)
3. (where r does not occur free for x in A)

A valid scheme in the theory of equality which exhibits the same feature is

4.

Informally, if F is '=y', G is 'is Pegasus', and we substitute 'Pegasus' for y, then (4) appears to allow us to infer from 'everything identical with Pegasus is Pegasus' that something is identical with Pegasus. The problem comes from substituting nondesignating constants for variables: in fact, we cannot do this in standard formulations of first-order logic, since there are no nondesignating constants. Classically, ∃x(x=y) is deducible from the open equality axiom y=y by particularization (i.e. (3) above).

In free logic, (1) is replaced with

1b. , where E! is an existence predicate (in some but not all formulations of free logic, E!t can be defined as ∃y(y=t))

Similar modifications are made to other theorems with existential import (e.g. the Rule of Particularization becomes (Ar → (E!r → ∃xAx)).

Axiomatizations of free-logic are given in Hintikka (1959),[1] Lambert (1967), Hailperin (1957), and Mendelsohn (1989).

Interpretation

Karel Lambert wrote in 1967:[2]

"In fact, one may regard free logic... literally as a theory about singular existence, in the sense that it lays down certain minimum conditions for that concept." The question that concerned the rest of his paper was then a description of the theory, and to inquire whether it gives a necessary and sufficient condition for existence statements.

Lambert notes the irony in that Willard Van Orman Quine so vigorously defended a form of logic that only accommodates his famous dictum, "To be is to be the value of a variable," when the logic is supplemented with Russellian assumptions of description theory. He criticizes this approach because it puts too much ideology into a logic, which is supposed to be philosophically neutral. Rather, he points out, not only does free logic provide for Quine's criterion—it even proves it! This is done by brute force, though, since he takes as axioms and , which neatly formalizes Quine's dictum. So, Lambert argues, to reject his construction of free logic requires you to reject Quine's philosophy, which requires some argument and also means that whatever logic you develop is always accompanied by the stipulation that you must reject Quine to accept the logic. Likewise, if you reject Quine then you must reject free logic. This amounts to the contribution that free logic makes to ontology.

The point of free logic, though, is to have a formalism that implies no particular ontology, but that merely makes an interpretation of Quine both formally possible and simple. An advantage of this is that formalizing theories of singular existence in free logic brings out their implications for easy analysis. Lambert takes the example of the theory proposed by Wesley C. Salmon and George Nahknikian,[3] which is that to exist is to be self-identical.

See also

References

43 year old Petroleum Engineer Harry from Deep River, usually spends time with hobbies and interests like renting movies, property developers in singapore new condominium and vehicle racing. Constantly enjoys going to destinations like Camino Real de Tierra Adentro.

  • Lambert, Karel, 2003. Free logic: Selected essays. Cambridge Univ. Press.
  • -------, 2001, "Free Logics," in Goble, Lou, ed., The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic. Blackwell.
  • ------, 1997. Free logics: Their foundations, character, and some applications thereof. Sankt Augustin: Academia.
  • ------, ed. 1991. Philosophical applications of free logic. Oxford Univ. Press.
  • Morscher, Edgar, and Hieke, Alexander, 2001. New essays in free logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

External links

  1. Jaako Hintikka (1959). Existential Presuppositions and Existential Commitments. Journal of Philosophy 56 (3):125-137.
  2. Free Logic and the Concept of Existence by Karel Lambert, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, V.III, numbers 1 and 2, April 1967
  3. George Nahknikian and Wesley C. Salmon, "'Exists' as a Predicate" Philosophical Review Vol. 66: 1957 pp. 535-542