Pareto priority index

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search

The Leggett–Garg inequality,[1] named for Anthony James Leggett and Anupam Garg, is a mathematical inequality fulfilled by all macrorealistic physical theories. Here, macrorealism (macroscopic realism) is a classical worldview defined by the conjunction of two postulates:[1]

  1. Macrorealism per se: "A macroscopic object, which has available to it two or more macroscopically distinct states, is at any given time in a definite one of those states."
  2. Noninvasive measurability: "It is possible in principle to determine which of these states the system is in without any effect on the state itself, or on the subsequent system dynamics."

In quantum mechanics

In quantum mechanics, the Leggett–Garg inequality is violated, meaning that the time evolution of a system cannot be understood classically. The situation is similar to the violation of Bell's inequalities in Bell test experiments which plays an important role in understanding the nature of the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox. Here quantum entanglement plays the central role. The violation of Bell's inequalities rules out local hidden variable theories which attempt to restore the realism in the sense that definiteness of the outcome in a single measurement can be ensured by using a supplementary variable along with the wave function which can not be obtained in the standard Copenhagen Interpretation of quantum mechanics in its various formulations.

As well as Einstein's famous "God does not play dice" objection to quantum mechanics, there was Einstein's still more fundamental objection that the Moon is still there when nobody looks. If the violation of the Leggett–Garg inequality can be demonstrated on the macroscopic scale, this would challenge even this notion of realism.

Two-state example

The simplest form of the Leggett–Garg inequality derives from examining a system that has only two possible states. These states have corresponding measurement values . The key here is that we have measurements at two different times, and one or more times between the first and last measurement. The simplest example is where the system is measured at three successive times . Now suppose, for instance, that there is a perfect correlation of 1 between times and . That is to say, that for N realisations of the experiment, the temporal correlation reads

We look at this case in some detail. What can be said about what happens at time ? Well, it is possible that , so that the if the value at , then it is also for both times and . It is also quite possible that that , so that the value at is flipped twice, and so has the same value at as it did at . So, we can have both and anti-correlated as long as we have and anti-correlated. Yet another possibility is that there is no correlation between and . That is we could have . So, although it is known that if at it must also be at , the value at may well as be determined by the toss of a coin. We define as . In these three cases, we have and , respectively.

All that was for 100% correlation between times and . In fact, for any correlation between these times . To see this, we note that

It is easily seen that for every realisation , the term in the parentheses must be less than or equal to unity, so that the result for the sum is also less than (or equal to) unity. If we have four distinct times rather than three, we have and so on. These are the Leggett–Garg inequalities. They say something definite about the relation between the temporal correlations of and the correlations between successive times in going from the start to the end.

In the derivations above, it has been assumed that the quantity Q, representing the state of the system, always has a definite value (macrorealism per se) and that its measurement at a certain time does not change this value nor its subsequent evolution (noninvasive measurability). A violation of the Leggett–Garg inequality implies that at least one of these two assumptions fails.

Experimental violations

The Leggett–Garg inequality is always violated on the microscopic scale. An example is given by Brukner and Kofler in.[2] However, they have also demonstrated that quantum violations can be found for arbitrarily large macroscopic systems. As an alternative to quantum decoherence, Brukner and Kofler are proposing a solution of the quantum-to-classical transition in terms of coarse-grained quantum measurements under which usually no violation of the Leggett–Garg inequality can be seen anymore.[3][4]

One of the most promising proposed experiments for demonstrating a violation of macroscopic realism employs superconducting quantum interference devices. There, using Josephson junctions, one should be able to prepare macroscopic superpositions of left and right rotating macroscopically large electronic currents in a superconducting ring. Under sufficient suppression of decoherence one should be able to demonstrate a violation of the Leggett–Garg inequality.[5]

A criticism of some other proposed experiments on the Leggett–Garg inequality is that they do not really show a violation of macrorealism because they are essentially about measuring spins of individual particles.[6] However, this book cites later work by Mermin [7] and Braunstein and Mann [8] which would be better tests of macroscopic realism, but warns that the experiments may be complex enough to admit unforeseen loopholes in the analysis.

Related inequalities

The four-term Leggett–Garg inequality can be seen to be similar to the CHSH inequality. Moreover, equalities were proposed by Jaeger et al.[9]

See also

References

43 year old Petroleum Engineer Harry from Deep River, usually spends time with hobbies and interests like renting movies, property developers in singapore new condominium and vehicle racing. Constantly enjoys going to destinations like Camino Real de Tierra Adentro.

  1. 1.0 1.1 Quantum Mechanics versus macroscopic realism: is the flux there when nobody looks? A. J. Leggett and Anupam Garg. Phys. Rev. Lett. 54, 857 (1985)
  2. http://www.fjfi.cvut.cz/workshop/Workshop_Prague_2008/presentations/Brukner_measurements.pdf
  3. Classical world arising out of quantum physics under the restriction of coarse-grained measurements. Johannes Kofler and Caslav Brukner. Phys. Rev. Lett. 99, 180403 (2007), ArXiv 0609079 [quant-ph] Sept. 2006 http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0609079
  4. The conditions for quantum violation of macroscopic realism. Johannes Kofler and Caslav Brukner. Phys. Rev. Lett. 101, 090403 (2008), ArXiv 0706.0668 [quant-ph] June 2007 http://arxiv.org/abs/0706.0668
  5. Testing the limits of quantum mechanics: motivation, state of play, prospects. A. J. Leggett. J. Phys.: Condens. Matter 14, R414-R451 (2002)
  6. Foundations and Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Gennaro Auletta and Georgio Parisi, World Scientific, 2001 ISBN 981-02-4614-5, ISBN 978-981-02-4614-3
  7. Extreme quantum entanglement in a superpostion of macroscopically distinct states. David Mermin, Phys. Rev. Lett. 65 1838-1840 (1990)
  8. Noise in Mermin's n-particle Bell inequality. Braunstein, S.L. and Mann, A., Phys. Rev. A 47, R2427-R2430 (1993)
  9. Bell type equalities for SQUIDs on the assumptions of macroscopic realism and non-invasive measurability. Gregg Jaeger, Chris Viger and Sahotra Sarkar. Phys. Lett. A 210, 5-10 (1996)