In algebraic geometry, the theorem on formal functions states the following:[1]
- Let
be a proper morphism of noetherian schemes with a coherent sheaf
on X. Let
be a closed subscheme of S defined by
and
formal completions with respect to
and
. Then for each
the canonical (continuous) map:

- is an isomorphism of (topological)
-modules, where
The theorem is used to deduce some other important theorems: Stein factorization and a version of Zariski's main theorem that says that a proper birational morphism into a normal variety is an isomorphism. Some other corollaries (with the notations as above) are:
Corollary:[2] For any
, topologically,

where the completion on the left is with respect to
.
Corollary:[3] Let r be such that
for all
. Then

Corollay:[4] For each
, there exists an open neighborhood U of s such that

Corollary:[5] If
, then
is connected for all
.
The theorem also leads to the Grothendieck existence theorem, which gives an equivalence between the category of coherent sheaves on a scheme and the category of coherent sheaves on its formal completion (in particular, it yields algebralizability.)
Finally, it is possible to weaken the hypothesis in the theorem; cf. Illusie. According to Illusie (pg. 204), the proof given in EGA III is due to Serre. The original proof (due to Grothendieck) was never published.
The construction of the canonical map
Let the setting be as in the lede. In the proof one uses the following alternative definition of the canonical map.
Let
be the canonical maps. Then we have the base change map of
-modules
.
where
is induced by
. Since
is coherent, we can identify
with
. Since
is also coherent (as f is proper), doing the same identification, the above reads:
.
Using
where
and
, one also obtains (after passing to limit):

where
are as before. One can verify that the composition of the two maps is the same map in the lede. (cf. EGA III-1, section 4)
Notes
References